AN EXAMINATION OF THE UNDERLYING MORAL FRAMEWORKS OF ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY by ANNA THERESA BERESFORD A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN THE INTERDISCIPLINARY HUMANITIES in THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES Master of Arts We accept this thesis as conforming to the required standard ............................................................................... Dr. Myron A. Penner, Ph.D.; Thesis Supervisor ................................................................................ Dr. Grant Havers, Ph.D.; Second Reader ................................................................................ Dr. Robert Doede, Ph.D.; External Examiner TRINITY WESTERN UNIVERSITY Date July, 2017 © Anna Beresford ABSTRACT The vast amount of environmental philosophy texts offers many solutions and methods with which to approach ecological crises. Quite often though, these solutions are contradictory. Environmental awareness is often cited as the justification for many competing strategies, policies, and everyday actions. With so many conflicting and confusing reports, it is difficult to know how we should relate to nature or which approach to adopt; which method is both plausible and ethical. In this paper I discuss and analyse the views of radical ecology and holistic environmental ethics in order to identify their underlying moral frameworks to ascertain their practical consequences with regards to humanity. In the first chapter I present and analyse the radical ecology position inclusive of deep ecology, social ecology, and ecofeminism. I then isolate and analyse the underlying ethical framework of the radical ecology position and evaluate what the costs and benefits of this position regarding humanity. In the second chapter I present and analyse the holistic environmental ethic and then proceed with the same method as chapter one. In the third chapter I introduce a philosophical argument for the necessity of making the concern for persons the initial step in ecological attitudes. I then revisit the structures of radical ecology and holistic environmental ethics with this view in mind. I ultimately argue that although both radical ecology and the holistic environmental ethics view of nature offer valuable insight that they are too quick to dismiss the uniqueness of the human condition. Thus these methods must be modified, with a view to a humanistic approach, in order to be logically coherent and provide plausible frameworks from which to encounter the natural world. 2 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS There are many people who helped me in the completion of the MAIH program and this thesis specifically. Primarily I would like to thank my supervisor, Myron Penner, for his guidance in this thesis and throughout the entirety of my MA. He demanded nothing less than my best while offering continuous support in the process. His precision and clarity of thought gave direction to this thesis. He spent many hours meeting with me for philosophical conversations and guiding my thought and research. Additionally, he has a love of truth that is inspiring and to be witness to this, I am especially grateful. Grant Havers as a professor and a reader on this thesis provided many scholarly recommendations and thought provoking comments. His knowledge of Enlightenment philosophy helped to establish this paper as a conversation between environmental philosophers and their intellectual predecessors. Robert Doede asked thoughtful questions and gave me many recommendations for how to continue with the ideas of this thesis and how to integrate them in other areas of research. Mr. Schintgen first instilled a love of philosophy in me and provided me with philosophical principles and tools that I have used over the course of my academic career. I would also like to thank Jayne Cummins, knower of all things, who provided unending logistical aid and alleviated much stress over the completion of this dissertation. My siblings and friends who engaged with and endured many philosophical conversations as I wrestled with these ideas during the writing of this thesis, without whom I could not have completed this paper. Finally, my parents, David and Theresa, who have tirelessly encouraged and supported me through this MA program offering moral, spiritual, intellectual, and financial support far surpassing nature’s mandates. This project is as much theirs as mine. For any flaws that lie herein I am, of course, responsible. 3 TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction I. The General Introduction II. Statement of the Problem III. Significance of the Problem A. Significance for Environmental Philosophy B. Significance for Daily Practice IV. Plan of Research A. Methodology B. Definitions C. Chapter Summary V. Conclusions Chapter 1: Radical Ecology I. The Necessity of a Paradigm Shift: Response to the Ecological Crisis A. Deep Ecology 1. Arne Naess 2. George Sessions 3. Bill Devall B. Social Ecology 1. Murray Bookchin C. Ecofeminism 1. Karren J. Warren 2. Carolyn Merchant II. Analysis A. What are the Operative Moral Frameworks of the Radical Ecology Movement? 1. What must be assumed true in order for their claims to be true? B. What are the Implications and Possible Problems of the Radical Ecology Moral Framework? 1. The Benefit of the Radical Ecology Ethic to the Human Species 2. The Cost of the Radical Ecology Ethic to the Human Species III. Conclusion Chapter 2: Biocentrism or Environmental Ethics I. The Problem with Anthropocentrism and the Need for a Biocentric Solution A. Biocentric Holism 1. Aldo Leopold 2. J. Baird Callicott 3. Holmes Rolston III 4. Paul Taylor B. Utilitarians Briefly Considered – Peter Singer II. Analysis 4 A. What are the Operative Moral Frameworks of the Biocentric Environmental Ethics Movement 1. What Must be Assumed True in Order for Their Claims to be True? B. What are the Implications and Possible Problems for the Biocentric Environmental Ethics Framework? 1. The Benefit of the Biocentric Environmental Ethic to the Human Species 2. The Cost of the Biocentric Environmental Ethics and Internal Logical Issues III. Conclusion Chapter 3: Shifting the Moral Structure for Environmental Ethics: Re-Thinking the Human Factor I. Should We Reconsider the Human Element? A. Aldo Leopold Revisited with Notes from Berthold-Bond B. Small is Beautiful: The Need for the Human Scale 1. E.F. Schumacher 2. Oliver Rackham & Robert MacFarlane 3. P. B. Medawar & the Human Aspect of Induction 4. Wendell Berry II. Re-adjusting the moral structures A. Re-adjustment to Radical Ecology B. Re-adjustment to Holistic Environmental Ethics Conclusion 5 I. INTRODUCTION II. THE GENERAL WORRY Environmental concern has become the topic of general debate in the public forum in the last forty to fifty years. Often cited as the inspiration to the widespread recognition of environmental awareness is Rachel Carson’s Silent Spring (1962). In Silent Spring Carson brought to the public attention scientific evidence linking the death of millions of birds to the widespread use of the pesticide DDT and advocates for the necessity of rethinking our attitudes towards the use of nature.1 Additionally, authors such as Henry David Thoreau, William Morris, and Aldo Leopold offered ground breaking ideas on the necessity of caring for and rediscovering the natural world through paradigm shifting approaches. Likewise, the scientific field of ecology blossomed, further contributing to the call for the discipline of environmental philosophy. In response to the awakening of environmental consciences emerged many and varied solutions and as many diagnoses of the problem. The study of environmental philosophy and the ecological crisis have become conversations of global proportions in an effort to identify causes and possible solutions. There are conflicting and contradictory narratives for both the cause and the solution of the environmental crisis. George Sessions blames Western culture for the root of the environmental problem, as he explains: “Western cultural ideas of the domination and control of nature has shaped the development and thrust of modern science and technology.”2 Furthermore, using the thought of Lynn White Jr., Sessions argues “Because ‘modern science and technology 1 Carson’s account of the connection of DDT to the death of birds, although it inspired many into environmental action, is controversial as she chose particularly lurid examples and her action resulted in the death of many children in developing nations due to the ban of DDT. For an article that details the direct effect of DDT on birds see: Joseph J. Nocera, Jules M. Blais, David V. Beresford, Leah K. Finity, Christopher Grooms, Lynda E. Kimpe, Kurt Kyser, Neal Michelutti, Matthew W. Reudink, John P. Smol, “Historical pesticide applications coincided with an altered diet of aerially foraging insectivorous chimney swifts,” The Royal Society, http://rspb.royalsocietypublishing.org/content/early/2012/04/15/rspb.2012.0445. 2 George Sessions, “The Deep Ecology Movement: A Review,” Environmental Review: ER Vol. 11, No. 2 (1987), 105-125, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3984023. 106. 6 are permeated with orthodox Christian arrogance toward nature’ we will have a worsening crisis ‘until we reject the Christian axiom that nature has no reason for existence save to serve man.’”3 For Sessions, as for most deep ecologists, Christianity and Western culture are the source of the environmental problem. Alternatively, Kate Rigby argues that, “most obviously, it is important to note that the West does not have a monopoly on ecological errancy.”4 Meanwhile there are equally conflicting ideas as to the proper solution to environmental problems. Arne Naess argues that we can agree that “The flourishing of human life and cultures is compatible with a substantially smaller human population. [And] The flourishing of non-human life requires a smaller human population.”5 Environmental concern is cited as justification for global policies and governments, inspiring global conferences and discussions. While at the same time environmental interests are used as the justification of small-scale local policy and practice, as Roger Scruton says, “The more distant the legislature from the people the greater will be the distortion.”6 It is a marketing ploy used to sell products as well as to limit the consumption of goods. Many jobs have been created in the interest of environmental consciousness and as many prevented in the name of conservation. Impassioned and even hostile debate affirming and denying environmental crises have arisen dividing and uniting countries, cities, and local communities. There are three main branches or fields of study, offering different methods or approaches of environmentalism. The main branches are: 1) radical ecology, which includes deep ecology, ecofeminism, and social ecology; 2) biocentric environmental ethics, generally 3 Ibid. Kate Rigby, “Ecocriticism,” Literary and Cultural Criticism at the Twenty-First Century, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 151-178, 157. 5 Arne Naess, “The Deep Ecological Movement: Some Philosophical Aspects,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, Michael E. Zimmerman, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 193-211, 197. 6 Roger Scruton, How to Think Seriously About the Planet, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012, 98. 4 7 speaking, which is concerned mostly with holistic concepts of nature although does contain some individualists accounts as well; 3) and anthropocentric reformism.7 The radical ecology approach maintains that we need a paradigm shifting, revolutionary approach regarding our human relationship towards and the understanding of nature. The general biocentric environmental ethics approach – both holistic and individualistic – argues that we need to combat the anthropocentric traditional understanding of ethics and instead employ a bio or eco centric approach. Anthropocentric reform primarily argues that the roots of the environmental problems are not the result of anthropocentrism, but are the result of greed, ignorance, or general malintent. As such what is needed is the reform of government policy, an increase in education, and the encouragement of responsible stewardship. This view, generally speaking, considers the natural world as valuable only insofar as it has use to the human population. In the face of so many contradictory theories or approaches to how to proceed regarding the environmental crisis, we are often left feeling overwhelmed by deciphering which approach is presenting the truthful tale, and thus at a loss as to how to act. But we are also left with the knowledge that something must be done. We must take some action. But to whom should we turn? Which theorists or schools of thought present us with an honest and practical approach to deal with the environmental issues? III. STATEMENT OF THE PROBLEM Environmental philosophers rarely state the moral framework from which they are theorizing.8 Similarly though, our ethics do not exist within a vacuum; there are underlying assumptions that 7 Michael E Zimmerman, “General Introduction,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1998, 3-5. 8 Peter Singer explicitly mentions that he is working from within a utilitarian moral framework and that his praxis corresponds accordingly. Peter Singer, Practical Ethics. Second Edition, Melbourne: Cambridge University Press, 1999. 8 we have towards life that influence the way that we view morality.9 Conversely, our ethical assumptions guide our actions. Thus each of the approaches to environmentalism above make assumptions regarding the nature of ethics, each in turn relying on different moral structures. These moral structures require further that they make assumption regarding the nature of human beings and our relationship with the natural world. With the expansive amount of literature and policy regarding environmental action, how are we to adopt an attitude or philosophical approach to nature? It is often difficult to identify the normative implications with regards to our lives and the lives of other human beings, as well as the implications for the rest of the biotic community. In my thesis I will analyse the moral frameworks underlying the fields of radical ecology and holistic environmental ethics respectively. I will uncover and analyse the implications that they hold regarding the human species. I will determine further if and where these frameworks should be adapted with regard to human application. I introduce a philosophical argument for the necessity of making the concern for persons the initial step in ecological attitudes. I then revisit the structures of radical ecology and holistic environmental ethics with this view in mind. I ultimately argue that although both radical ecology and the holistic environmental ethics view of nature offer valuable insight that they are too quick to dismiss the uniqueness of the human condition. Thus these methods must be modified, with a view to a humanistic approach, in order to be logically coherent and provide plausible frameworks from which to encounter the natural world. SIGNIFICANCE OF THE PROBLEM A. Significance for the Environmental Philosophy 9 A point also referred to my Michael P. Nelson, in “Aldo Leopold, Environmental Ethics, and the Land Ethic.” Wildlife Society Bulletin (1973-2006) Vol. 26, No. 4 (1998) 741-744. 9 There is a vast amount of literature circulating regarding environmentalism. Although the various positions offer philosophical arguments, quite often the language of thinkers is ambiguous, focused entirely on practice rather than theory, or even mystical. Identifying the theoretical ethical structures necessitate that the different methods be understood with clarity regarding their logical coherence. Furthermore, by identifying the ethical frameworks from which the approaches are operating, provides three possibilities concerning the theories: 1) it connects a relatively new environmental philosophy with an established ethical theory, which opens it to the possibility of stronger support from the expansive ethical canon or critique depending on where one’s views align; 2) if the environmental philosophy is completely radical and not operating on any classical ethical worldview, identifying the structure provides clarity through which to view the strengths, weaknesses, or possible internal contradictions within this new approach; 3) if it is a combination of both, built on an existing moral structure but with significant modifications, we can identify whether it is logically consistent as a theory or whether it requires further modifications. The focus on the cost/benefit analysis with regards to humanity will identify exactly what is at stake for the person or persons who adopt or promote the different philosophical approaches. Additionally, the normative application with regards to humanity will offer insight with how to practically apply aspects of the different methods under review. B. Significance for Daily Practice We are encouraged daily to adopt practices to aid in averting the ecological crisis. Identifying the underlying moral framework and the implications that they have, specifically for humans, will aid in our ability to discern whether or not an environmental philosophy is consistent with our existing ethical practices. If so, allowing us to adopt a more eco-friendly and knowledgeable way 10 of life. If not, it will provide reasons to consider whether our current ethical assumptions or our possible environmental approach should be modified. IV. PLAN OF RESEARCH A. Methodology To quote Arnes Naess, “One should not expect too much from definitions of movements; think, for example, of terms like “conservatism,” “liberalism,” or the “feminist movement.”10 The same critique can be applied to “environmentalism” as well. As such, I will begin by looking at the positions presented by the founders or most influential thinkers within the different philosophies. For example for the deep ecology movement I will look at the writings of Arne Naess, George Sessions, and Bill Devall. While for the holistic environmental ethics position I will consider the writings of Aldo Leopold, J. Baird Callicott, and Holmes Rolston III. Once I have presented the views of the respective movements, I will analyse the underlying moral structures on which the philosophies are built. Through analysis of the moral frameworks I will discuss the assumed ethical code which the respective contrasting approaches hold. By isolating the ethical framework one can more clearly understand the implications that the positions present. Often the result or the practical implications of a method are obscure, but when only the values are present it is much easier to see what is at stake and entailed by adoption of the method. Given that the purpose of this project is to ascertain whether or not positions should be adopted with respect to their cost or benefit towards humanity, I then consider what is entailed by the different approaches concerning humanity. Finally I introduce philosophical arguments that show the necessity of first acknowledging the uniqueness of the human species and the 10 Arnes Naess, “The Deep Ecology Movement: Some Philosophical Aspects,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1998, 193-211, 196. 11 necessity of returning to a human scale in order to resolve the conflicts contained in the radical ecology and biocentric environmental ethics structures. Definitions 1. Anthropocene: Relating to or referring to the current geological age. “The Age of Man.” First used by ecologist Eugene F. Stoermer.11 2. Anthropocentric: (1) Considering human beings as the most significant entity of the universe. (2) Interpreting or regarding the world in terms of human values and experiences.12 3. Biocentrism: The view or belief that the rights and needs of humans are not more important than those of other living things.13 4. Biodiversity: The variety of all forms of life, from genes to species, through to the broad scale of ecosystems.14 5. Cartesian Dualism: A theory or system of thought that regards a domain of reality in terms of two independent principles, especially mind and matter. The mind and the material body are completely different types of substances that interact with each other.15 6. Deep Ecology: A movement originally developed by the Norwegian philosopher Arne Naess. It emphasizes that human beings are only part of the ecology of this planet, and believe that only by understanding our unity with the whole of nature 11 Holmes Rolston, III, “The Anthropocene! Beyond the Natural?” Stephen M. Gardiner and Allen Thompson, The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics, New York, Oxford University press, 2017, 62. 12 Merriam Webster: https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/anthropocentric. 13 English Oxford Living Dictionaries. https://en.oxforddictionaries.com/definition/biocentrism. 14 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, first published June 11, 2013 https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/biodiversity/. 15 While Descartes may have intended his cogito to refer to a distinction between mind and body rather than two completely different substances, environmental philosophy interprets the cause of the subjugation of the material world as stemming from the substance dualist interpretation of Descartes’ thought. Since substance dualism is the main interpretation among environmental philosophy it will also be the definition used throughout this paper. 12 can we come to achieve full realization of our humanity. Deep ecology believes that all organisms are equal: Human beings have no greater value than any other creature, for we are just ordinary citizens in the biotic community, with no more rights than amoebae or bacteria.16 7. Ecology: (1) The science concerned with the interactions of living organisms with each other and with their environment, also called bionomics. (2) The system within the environment as it relates to organisms living in it.17 8. Ecofeminism: There is no single definition of ecofeminism. Ecofeminists agree that the domination of women and the domination of nature are fundamentally connected and that environmental efforts are therefore integral to work to overcome the oppression of women. Ecofeminists do not seek equality with men as such, but aim for the liberation of women as women. Central to this liberation is the recognition of the value of the activities traditionally associated with women; childbirth, nurturing, and the whole domestic arena.18 9. Radical Ecology: The movement which claims that their analyses disclose the conceptual, attitudinal, social, political, and cultural origins of the ecological crisis. It argues that only a revolutionary or a cultural paradigm shift can save the planet from ecological devastation.19 10. Social Ecology: founded by Murray Bookchin, social ecology claims that the environmental crisis is a result of the hierarchical organization of power and the 16 The Green Fuse/Topics: http://www.thegreenfuse.org/deepecology.htm. Biology Online: http://www.biology-online.org/dictionary/Ecology. 18 The Green Fuse/Topics, http://www.thegreenfuse.org/ecofem.htm. 19 Michael Zimmerman, “General Introduction,” Environmental Ethics: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1-16, 4. 17 13 authoritarian mentality rooted in the structures of our society. The Western ideology of dominating the natural world arise from the social relationships.20 B. Chapter Summary In chapter 1 I will present the main positions of the radical ecology movement, from the positions of deep ecology, social ecology, and ecofeminism respectively. I will then analyse the moral framework upon which the radical ecology movement is built. With the moral framework in view I will make comparisons to existing ethical theories identifying which are the most influential to the radical ecology movement. Of particular focus will be the implications for the human species. The ultimate goal of the analysis of the moral frameworks is to determine the cost/benefit with regards to humans and where or whether aspects of radical ecology movement should be adopted as daily practice. Chapter 2 deals with the holistic environmental ethic view. I will present the main arguments of this movement through the writing of Leopold, Callicott, and Rolston III. Once the main ideas are presented I adopt the same approach as Chapter 1 and analyse the moral framework specifically with an eye towards the cost and benefit towards humanity. Ultimately, I will determine which aspects of the holistic approach should be adopted and which (if any) require further modification. In Chapter 3 I reconsider the thought of Aldo Leopold with a second interpretation of his view of humanity. I also introduce the thinkers who advocate for concern for individual persons as the necessary first step in the resolving ecological problems. The ideas are presented through E F Schumacher, Oliver Rackham, P. B. Medawar, Wendell Berry, and Daniel Berthold-Bond. With the introduction of thought focused on a deeper concern for humanity I suggest that the application and theories of radical ecology and holistic 20 The Green Fuse/Topics: http://www.thegreenfuse.org/socialecology.htm. 14 environmental ethics would benefit from a consideration of these human-scaled and humancentred philosophies. V. CONCLUSIONS I conclude by arguing that although the methods of radical ecology and holistic environmental ethics offer insightful and important ideas, they must first have concern for the human species and return to a human scale in order to resolve the logical contradictions they contain and in order to be applied in a plausible and ethical manner. 15 Chapter 1: Radical Ecology I. The Necessity of a Paradigm Shift: Response to the Ecological Crisis There are many different versions of theories which can claim the title “radical ecology.” The underlying feature of radical ecology is the assertion that we need a paradigm shift in order to engage with and resolve the current ecological crisis. The understanding of humanity’s place in the world, our importance, our hierarchical standing, the concerns which we have, our understanding of ourselves must change in order to deal with the state that we caused in the world. As stated by Edgar D. Mitchell upon the return mission of Apollo 14, in reference to how to resolve the eco-crisis what we need “is a transformation of consciousness.”21 While there are many different creeds or responses contained within the “radical ecology movement,” the movement is made coherent through the agreement of the following reasons.22 First, as Michael Zimmerman states, “they claim that their analyses disclose the conceptual, attitudinal, social, political, and cultural origins of the ecological crisis. Second, they argue that only a revolution or cultural paradigm shift can save the planet from ecological devastation.”23 Unifying to the radical ecology movement and the diversity of writers within, from deep ecologist to ecofeminists to social ecologists, is the assertion that we must shift the cultural paradigm and that they have 21 Edgar D. Mitchell, originally cited in Roberts, 2011. Drengson, A., Devall, B., & Schroll, M. A. (2011). Drengson, A., Devall, B., & Schroll, M. A. (2011). The deep ecology movement: Origins, development, and future prospects (toward a transpersonal ecosophy). International Journal of Transpersonal Studies, 30(1-2), 101–117.. International Journal of Transpersonal Studies, 30 (1)., 103 Retrieved from http://digitalcommons.ciis.edu/ijtstranspersonalstudies/vol30/iss1/11. 22 While there are many important and different aspects of the radical ecology movement, this chapter will deal largely with deep ecology, touching on ecofeminism and social ecology in relation to deep ecology. This is not because these methods are any less important, but simply because the scope of this paper will not allow for an in depth analysis of all three and deep ecology claims to include ecofeminism and adopts the most paradigm shifting approach. 23 Michael E. Zimmerman, “General Introduction,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, Toronto: Prentice Hall, 1998, 1-6, 4. 16 identified the origins and cause of the crisis that we face within the current, mainstream, paradigm. Deep Ecology The Deep Ecology Movement 1. Arne Naess Norwegian mountaineer and philosopher, Arne Naess, invented the term “deep ecology” to distinguish it from “shallow ecology,” in his article “The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary,” in 1973.24 Contrary to “shallow ecology,” which Naess views as simply an extension of North American and European “use-value” anthropocentric ethics, Deep Ecology calls for a upheaval or reordering of our understanding of our place in the cosmos and our value systems. Like any other “movement,” it is difficult to give an exact and comprehensive definition of Deep Ecology; Naess argues that each member has slightly varying conceptions as to how it should be defined. However, there are eight underlying principles which make up the Deep Ecology movement. While people differ on the importance or placement of particular principles or the various aspects of them, the principles themselves, Naess argues, all deep ecologists uphold. Thus the principles themselves provide the most clarity in terms of defining the movement. Each self-identifying deep ecologist agrees on some combination of the following: 1) The well-being and flourishing of human and non-human life on Earth have value in themselves regardless of the usefulness of the non-human world for the human purposes. 24 Michael P. Nelson, “Deep Ecology,” Encyclopedia of Environmental Ethics and Philosophy, 206-211, 206. 17 2) Richness and diversity of life forms contribute to the realization of these values and are also values in and of themselves. 3) Humans have no right to reduce this richness and diversity except to satisfy vital needs. 4) The flourishing of human life and cultures is compatible with a substantially smaller human population. The flourishing of non-human life requires a smaller human population. 5) Present human interference with the non-human world is excessive, and the situation is rapidly worsening. 6) Policies must therefore be changed. These policies affect basic economic, technological, and ideological structures. The resulting state of affairs will be deeply different from the present. 7) The ideological change will be mainly that of appreciating life quality (dwelling in situations of inherent value) rather than adhering to the increasingly higher standard of living. There will be a profound awareness of the difference between bigness and greatness. 18 8) Those who ascribe to the foregoing points have an obligation directly or indirectly to try to implement the necessary changes.25 While Naess provides the principles and explanation for Deep Ecology, Harold Glasser argues that there are many thinkers who misinterpret or misunderstand what Naess entails in his thought. Through discussion of Naess’ deep ecology in “Demystifying the Critiques of Deep Ecology,” Glasser provides clarification and defenses to the common misconceptions of Naess’ thought and provides his own nuanced understanding of Naess to add further clarity. Significantly, he argues that while deep ecology require more care for other species, that this does not justify less care for humans. Additionally, population reduction or control does not entail draconian measures.26 While it is necessary that the human population be reduced this reduction does not justify maltreatment of living persons. 2. George Sessions In George Sessions’ review of the deep ecology movement, he describes the contribution to deep ecology by Lynn White, Jr., which highlights what Sessions’ understanding of the root cause for the ecological crisis. White argues that Christianity provides the “justification” of an anthropocentric and subjugating view of nature.27 Until we rid the world of Christianity, we cannot hope to address the ecological crisis. Although White denounces Christianity, he does admire the thought and practice of St. Francis and thought that the solution to the environmental crisis was to adopt the ecological egalitarianism of St Francis. White’s article was reprinted 25 Arne Naess, The Deep Ecological Movement: Some Philosophical Aspects. Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology. Michael E. Zimmerman. New Jersey: Simon & Schuster, 1993, 196-97. 26 Harold Glasser, “Demystifying the Critiques of Deep Ecology.” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1998, 212-226. 27 Sessions is making reference to Lynn White Jr.’s “The Historical Roots of Our Ecological Crisis,” 1967. 19 many times as well as being published in several anthologies. Christian thinkers for the most part denounced White’s thinking. Sessions continues that since the 1960, radical ecologists have taken inspiration from writers such as “Thoreau and Muir, from the Zen Buddhism of Huxley, Watts, and Snyder, and from the antiutopian social critiques of Huxley and Orwell.”28 Additionally, Michael Zimmerman interpreted and developed the thought and method of Heidegger through an ecological lens. While Stuart Hampshire, a scholar of Spinoza, used Spinozo’s pantheism to critique the anthropocentric exploitation of nature.29 Naess, also drawing on the work of Spinoza, developed his deep ecology from the concept of universal selfrealization. Sessions further explains that, from the writings of Arne Naess, George Session and Bill Devell distinguished between the deep ecology and shallow ecology methods and used this distinction and a basis for “classifying and describing the various ecophilosophical positions.”30 The ecological worldview, Sessions explains, questions the modern metaphysics and challenges us to rethink the method Western ethics entirely.31 Sessions offers considerable detail in regards to the necessity of a global approach to the ecological crisis, citing the need for a united effort to reduce the human population as the top priority in order to care for the earth. While, he states it is necessary not to compromise the dignity of humanity, it is the duty of the United Nations to give the “highest priority to 28 George Sessions, “The Deep Ecology Movement: A Review.” Environmental Review: ER Vol. 11 No. 2 (1987) 105-125. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3984023, 109. 29 Although Stuart Hampshire interprets Spinoza as a pantheist, as noted by Grant Havers, Spinoza makes a distinction between the universe and human nature, indicating that he did not advocate for pantheism. Baruch Spinoza, Ethics: An Edinburgh Philosophical Guide, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2010, 33. 30 George Sessions, “The Deep Ecology Movement: A Review.” Environmental Review: ER Vol. 11 No. 2 (1987) 105-125. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3984023, 113. 31 George Sessions, “The Deep Ecology Movement: A Review.” Environmental Review: ER Vol. 11 No. 2 (1987) 105-125. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3984023. 20 stabilizing the human population in the shortest time possible.”32 On a practical level, Sessions argues that progress has been made in recent years to stabilizing the human population saying, “birth control programs, including making contraceptives freely available to all who want them, have quite recently proven to be highly effective in dramatically reducing birthrates in certain Third World countries.”33 He then further states, “Third World countries should be encouraged to adopt as high a priority as possible on the establishment of ecosystem protection zones, and the protection of large areas of free nature.”34 Thus, as developing countries have more undeveloped areas they should be encouraged to maintain these areas as undeveloped and since they also have the fastest rising populations they, most of all, should be encouraged to stabilize their populations. 3. Bill Devall Bill Devall emphasises the importance of a paradigm shift to defuse an anthropocentric hierarchy. As he states, in “The Deep Long Range Ecology Movement 1960-2000 A Review,” “When they accept slogans such as “Earth First!” or “thinking like a mountain,” they are rejecting human hubris and placing Homo sapiens, as a species, in a more modest position in the cosmos.”35 He states that while there is tension within politics as there is bound to be in the overturning of any paradigm, “The practice of deep ecology includes both personal lifestyles and community lifestyles.”36 Thus politics plays a crucial part in DEM [Deep Long Range Ecology Movement], as in public policy we can start to think of policies for the wellbeing of all, the good 32 George Sessions, “Ecocentrism, Wilderness, and the Global Ecosystem Protection,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, Toronto: Prentice-Hall, 245-262, 259. 33 Ibid. 34 Ibid. 35 Bill Deval, “The Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement 1960-2000-A Review” Ethics & the Environment, Vol.6 No.1 (2001), 22. 36 Ibid, 24. 21 of the ecosystem as a whole. Additionally, like Sessions, Devall argues that this policy applies to developing and developed countries alike. While some critics argues that developing countries must primarily focus on problems of military conflict, poverty, gender equality, etc., Devall argues that it is DEM’s emphasis on long term sustainability that makes it essential for developing countries. He states, “On the contrary, supporters of the DEM conclude it is most appropriate for the Third World because of its emphasis on long-range sustainability of natural systems within which humans as well as all other species must dwell.”37 The natural integration of the human species with the rest of the ecosystems provides a means of championing social equality, whereas social justice movements often cause further subjugation of the nonhuman world as a result of their emphasis on human equality. As he states, “It is the human species that must learn to live together as a civilized and mutually supportive community. To focus on the development of civility among the human species is not to inflate unduly the importance of humanity within the ecosystem of life on Earth; rather it is to recognize how dangerous the human race is to the viability of the Earth's ecosystem.”38 The emphasis should be on the unity of the ecosystem as a whole, or a globalist approach (inclusive of the nonhuman) to solving such problems. Devall’s view of the most significant aspects of deep ecology is made apparent through his discussion and interpretation of John Muir’s works. Devall argues that Muir’s greatest contribution to ecology is his recognition of the essential unity of all things. Devall states, “In his writings he uses the word God, Nature, And Beauty almost interchangeably.”39 This unity is 37 Ibid, 27. Ibid, 33. 39 Bill Devall, “John Muir as Deep Ecologist,” Environmental Review: KER, vol. 6, no. 1, (Spring, 1982), pp. 63-86, 66. Oxford University Press on behalf of Forest History Society and American Society for Environmental History. Accessed: April 3, 2017. www.jstor.org/stable/3984050. 38 22 especially significant for epistemological reasons. Muir offers a way of knowing beyond reductionist classifications. As Devall states, “For Muir [. . .] Nature is only partly described by models. The map is not the territory […] He went beyond ecology as reductionist science, as theories of interrelationships to begin blinding with the landscape.”40 In immersing oneself in the landscape and seeing it as a whole, while the language becomes somewhat mystical, it allows for and experience and knowledge beyond categories. Devall argues that Muir’s travels in the wild allowed for a transformation of consciousness bringing him into self-realization. In this manner ecology moves beyond a use or manipulation and offers a way of being in the world. The following quotation from Devall regarding Muir offers a clear understanding of what Devall considers essential to Deep Ecology, “Muir recognized that an objective perspective would be different from the dualism so prevalent in Western philosophy since the seventeenth century. In Muir’s participatory science, his “wandering from flower to flower” was extending unity, flowing from the Tao.”41 In this passage Devall expresses his admiration for Muir and though this shows what he considers to be essential to Deep Ecology, namely, a rejection of the dualist Enlightenment philosophy, and self-realization through recognition of the unity of all things, which he expresses through Taoist philosophy.42 Social Ecology 1. Murray Bookchin 40 Ibid, 66. Ibid, 78. 42 For a great introduction to Taoism see Keith Seddon’s, Lao Tzu & Tao Te Ching, Lulu: 2006. Additionally, while it is beneficial to examine Devall’s thought through his discussion of Muir, I disagree with his interpretation of Muir as Deep Ecologist and his interpretation of Taoism. Muir’s use of literary devices throughout his texts, particularly in My First Summer in the Sierra highlights a distinctly human way of knowing, further illustrating the uniqueness of humanity. Likewise, while Devall interprets Taoism as the foundation for Deep Ecology, I think a more accurate interpretation is to understand Taoism in Aristotelian terms of “act” and “potency.” 41 23 In his article “Social Ecology versus Deep Ecology: A Challenge for the Ecology Movement” Bookchin examines the tenants of the deep ecology and social ecology movements. Deep ecology, he argues has its foundation in an “original sin” theory that sees anthropocentrism as the plague upon the earth; “humanity” in its flourishing is the main cause of the environmental crisis. He argues that it promotes an eco-brutalism that justifies the starvation of the developing world in order to lighten the burden on ecological resources. Bookchin argues that deep ecology, championed by Naess, is a spiritual ideology, rather than intellectual movement, deriving its identity from Malthusian anti-humanism and “biocentric orgies.” Deep ecologists fail to recognize the value and uniqueness of human society, as seen through their claims that there is no difference between humanity and the members of the larger community of living species. This denial of the difference of humanity also fails to recognize that the environmental problem is ultimately a societal one. Instead, deep ecologists present us with, what Bookchin refers to as “eco-la-la,” in which humanity is dissolved into a “cosmic self” unified with bears, the earth, and the universe. This eco-la-la removes any remnant of concrete humanity and becomes something completely abstract, resulting in the loss of any notion of self. This loss of identity is something that is controlled by large corporations in a homogenizing movement under the guise of the “Connected Whole.” A problem for deep ecology, that Bookchin raises, is that in this transition from self-identity to the cosmic-self what are we to do with species such as smallpox or the AIDS virus – can they be eradicated? Or should they, in the interests of biocentrism be preserved? If not, who is to decide in the biocentric cosmos what species should be eradicated? Ultimately, Bookchin argues, the deep ecology promoted by Naess, Devall, and Sessions, through all of its over-spiritualised earth-loving language is little more than a justification of 24 social Darwinism, a method of keeping developing countries poor, and a “morally” acceptable justification of exploiting the poor and vulnerable. Conversely, Bookchin explains that social ecology is a “Green” movement, particularly leftist in its allegiance and focuses on humanism. Social ecology does not deny the uniqueness of the human species nor does it justify an “anthropocentricism” that in turn justifies the exploitation of more vulnerable humans and other species. The “marvel” nature has produced the “marvel” homo sapiens – homo sapiens are unique thinking species and yet entirely natural and as such do not resort to a dualism in their identity. Social Ecology focuses on the following: 1. Global government and social movements as the solution to the environmental problems we face. 2. Unwilling to accept the anti-humanist claims of the deep ecology movement. 3. An adherence to evolutionary theory and thus the dualistic humanity vs. the nonhuman world tension must be dispelled. In order to solve the environmental crisis Bookchins states that we must look to ecology and reject the anti-ecologist movement of deep ecology.43 A. Ecofeminism 1. Karren J. Warren Simply stated by Karren Warren and Jim Cheney in “Ecological Feminism and Ecosystem Ecology,” ecofeminism is feminist because it has the twofold commitment to critique male bias in ethics and to develop methods of analysis that are not male biased. Additionally, “ecofeminist 43 Bookchin, Murray. “Social Ecology versus Deep Ecology: A Challenge for the Ecology Movement,” Green Perspectives: Newsletter of the Green Program Project, 4 no. 5. Reprinted in Witoszek and Brennan 1999, 281-301. 25 ethics extends feminist ethical critiques of sexism and other social “ism of domination” to include critiques of “naturalism,” i.e., the unjustified domination of nonhuman animals and nature by humans.”44 Thus ecofeminism critiques anthropocentrism as well as androcentrism. In “The Power and the Promise of Ecological Feminism,” Karen Warren states that, “all ecofeminists agree about, then, is the way in which the logic of domination has functioned historically within patriarchy to sustain and justify the twin dominations of women and nature.”45 Warren presents an argument that she claims has been sanctioned by the dominant Western culture, stemming from a patriarchal society, which goes as follows: (1) Women are identified with nature and the realm of the physical; men are identified with the “human” and the realm of the mental. (2) Whatever is identified with nature and the realm of the physical is inferior to (“below”) whatever is identified with the “human” and the realm of the mental; or conversely, the latter is superior to (“above”) the former. (3) Thus, women are inferior to (“below”) men; or conversely, men are superior to (“above”) women. (4) For any X and Y, if X is superior to Y, then X is justified in subordinating Y. (5) Thus, men are justified in subordinating women.46 The above, which Warren refers to as the “logic of domination” is what all ecofeminists agree must be abolished in itself, in order to prevent feminism from becoming little more than a “support group.” 44 Karen J. Warren and Jim Cheney, “Ecological Feminism and Ecosystem Ecology,” Hypatia 6, no. 1, Ecological Feminism (1991): 179-197, 180. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3810040. Accessed: April 3, 2017. 45 Karen J. Warren, “The Power and the Promise of Ecological Feminism,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, Toronto: Prentice-Hall (1998): 325-344, 329. 46 Ibid, 328. 26 While one may argue that ecofeminism does not necessarily include the natural nonhuman realm, Warren disagrees and states that it is because the logic of domination itself is at question, any form of oppression must be ended. She states the argument as follows: (1) Feminism is a movement to end sexism. (2) But Sexism is conceptually linked with naturism (through an oppressive conceptual framework characterized by a logic of domination). (3) Thus, Feminism is (also) a movement to end naturism.47 It is the logic itself that is the fundamental issue. Thus one cannot claim to be “feminist” and not against naturism as well, as it is the conceptual framework of oppression that is the fundamental problem. Thus in order to be logically consistent, one must be both feminist and ecofeminist. Furthermore, the “logic of domination” refers to historically specific forms of social domination. While ecofeminism rejects phrases like “necessary and sufficient conditions” for ecofeminism as those concepts themselves, Warren argues, are born out of an androcentric conceptual framework, there are some “boundaries to ecofeminism in regards to environmental ethics. However, these boundaries are spoken in terms of minimum conditions, providing the basis but not the necessary internal structure. It is a base that comes from a dynamic multiplicity of voices. Feminism and Ecofeminism alike share the following minimum conditions: a) Anti-naturist b) Contextual – a shift from conceptual ethical frameworks applied to individuals to a concept of ethics growing out of defining relationships. c) It is pluralistic – it presupposes and maintains difference among humans and nonhumans alike. 47 Ibid, 331. 27 d) “Theory” is always “theory in process.” e) Inclusivist: it arises from listening to the voices of the outsider, the other, and the oppressed. f) Makes no attempt to offer an “objective” view point. g) Essential place for value, care, love, trust, friendship etc. – values that presuppose our relationships to others are essential to understanding the self. h) A re-imagining of what it means to be human and denial of individualism. Relationships are not extrinsic to humanity but an essential part of what it means to be human and to know the self.48 Warren’s notion of ecofeminism critiques the logic of domination that is “justified” through the hierarchical valuing of the rational/mind attributes of humanity (historically considered male attributes) over the physical/embodied/or feelings attributes (historically considered as feminine or nonhuman). Ecofeminism does not seek to rework the system of conceptual ethics, but instead to dispel the framework as a whole, as it is the framework itself that is morally impermissible. She provides a fluid, and contextual minimum requirement boundary for how to achieve ecofeminsism through listening to a multiplicity of voices and views. 2. Carolyn Merchant Carolyn Merchant’s insight into the historical attitudes regarding the human/nonhuman relationships is essential to understanding ecofeminism and radical ecology generally speaking. Her work The Death of Nature is a comprehensive history of the attitudes of humanity towards nature. It focuses specifically on the male/female analogies that undergird the different perspectives on nature and the role that humanity plays. Carolyn Merchant’s motivation in this 48 Ibid, 336-339. 28 work is to understand and investigate the worldview and the science that led to the dominion of nature by man, which in turn led to the current ecological problem that we are facing and its connection to science, technology, and the economy. Merchant begins the first chapter with the line, “the world we have lost was organic.”49 From ancient systems of thought, right up to the sixteenth century, nature was viewed as a living organism, the parts of which were dependent upon each other for proper functioning and flourishing of the everyday life. Within the organic theory of nature, nature was metaphorically understood to be female in two senses: a nurturing mother, caring for and looking after the needs of humanity; conversely, as a wild, untamed, disordered and chaotic woman, who could cause storms, droughts, famine, etc. on a whim. The first metaphor – nature as nurturing mother – was lost within the context of the scientific revolution and nature became viewed as a chaotic disordered female to be controlled by the male dominated science of the Enlightenment. The organic unity of thought in the Renaissance was rooted in Greek thought: Platonism, Aristotelianism, and Stoicism. The common denominator was that all parts of the cosmos were connected and interdependent as a living whole; changes of one part reflected in the changes of the others. Within this hierarchical yet interdependent model the well-being of each component was important as the well-being of the whole consisted in the flourishing of the parts. In order to live nature, that living unity, both male and female, must be kept well and alive. In “Nature as Disorder, Merchant says the following, “Nature-culture dualism is a key factor in Western civilization’s advance at the expense of nature.”50 The interpretation of nature as organic unity transitioned to an interpretation of nature as machine. Nature, in the new 49 Merchant, Carolyn. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology, and the Scientific Revolution. New York: Harper Collins Publishing, 1990, 1. 50 Ibid, 143. 29 mechanistic framework became something to tidy, to control, to fix. The male dominated sciences reduced nature to her most basic parts in an effort to exploit her. This reduction to a non-living mechanism is what Merchant refers to as the death of nature. Earlier in the text Merchant showed the progress of capitalism and how women’s role in production was removed. Similarly, the advances of science, particularly medicine, removed the role of women from reproduction. Midwifery became a male practice with scientific advancement because women were not allowed to study and so the midwife practices of women quickly became obsolete. Since the role of women in the conception of a child was, wrongly, considered to be entirely passive, with the scientific revolution, women became entirely passive in roles regarding production and reproduction. Merchant uses the analogy of forceps to capture the division between male and female participation: just as the forceps of the doctors had removed the midwife from childbirth and became a tool to penetrate and exploit that field of work, so too had science become a method of unveiling nature’s secrets in order to study, control, and manipulate.51 II. Analysis C. What are the Operative Moral Frameworks of the Radical Ecology Movement? 2. What Must be Assumed to be True in Order for Their Claims to be True? The primary assumption for the Radical Ecology movement is that the historical notions of how the human species relates to the nonhuman (or in the case of ecofeminism, how male persons relate to females and the rest of the nonhuman male species) has been immoral and 51 Merchant, Carolyn. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology, and the Scientific Revolution. New York: Harper Collins Publishing, 1990. 30 subjugating, and therefore that we need a completely new way of interacting with the nonhuman world. Entailed by this assumption is that all hierarchies are harm-inflicting human constructs; there are no natural hierarchies and that hierarchies are a method of “justified” subjugation of other persons or species. Thus any constructed hierarches must be dispelled. As Holy-Luczaj states, “all entities in the environment have an equal right to thrive. Interests of human beings are not considered by deep ecologists to be always inevitably superior to other beings as they are not justified by “higher” status of human life.”52 Further, the androcentric/anthropocentric “values” or “rights” moral framework must be dispelled and focus be placed more on the wellbeing of the whole. Although, the main critique ecofeminists have against deep ecology, as formulated by Zimmerman, is not that it is anthropocentric, but that it is inherently androcentric. Jim Cheney reformulates the ecofeminist critique, showing that they are not so concerned with the deep ecologist’s critique of anthropocentrism, but only that they do not do so in a strictly androcentric manner. However, Fox argues (which Cheney later acknowledges) the deep ecology movement does not rest on the language of intrinsic value or concepts of rights and thus is not subject to the androcentric critiques. Instead, deep ecologists are concerned with a wider state of being and as such with an expansive sense of self rather than rights or values. In this manner, it is similar to ecofeminism, which, Fox explains, is primarily concerned with the ethics of love, care, and friendship. One thing that the ecofeminists and deep ecologists agree on is that men have been far more implicated in the ecological crises than women. The deep ecologist’s main purpose is to unmask the anthropocentric ideology so that it can no longer be used as social domination for 52 Magdalena Holy-Luczaj, “Heidegger’s Support for Deep Ecology Reexamined Once Again: Ontological Egalitarianism, Or Farewell to the Great Chain of Being,” Ethics and the Environment 20 no. 1, (2015): 45-66. Indiana University Press. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2979/ethicsenviro.20.1.45. Accessed: March 4, 2017. 31 any group or class.53 Thus the dispelling of any hierarchy is the foundational assumption within radical ecology. As explicitly stated above by Naess, Sessions, and Devall, the practice of deep ecology involves devoting work to “stabilizing” the human population. As highlighted, especially by Sessions, the most important and significant method of carrying out the duties of the deep ecology movement is to reduce the human population. As principle eight in Naess’ list states, “Those who ascribe to the foregoing points have an obligation directly or indirectly to try to implement the necessary changes,” and thus, as the other principles can only be attained or implemented through the reduction of the human population, that is priority one in terms of practice. Thus each Deep Ecology must directly or indirectly work to reduce the human population. Conversely, anything that contributes to the growth of the human population must be avoided as this directly opposed all of the eight platform principles of Deep Ecology specifically, and radical ecology generally. However, it must be noted, as argued by Harold Glasser that decreasing populations do not entail draconian measures. D. What are the Positive Implications and Possible Problems of the Radical Ecology Moral Framework? 3. The Benefit of the Radical Ecology Ethic to the Human Species The main benefit of the radical ecology movement is that it offers a method for dissolving the human-constructed division between humanity and the rest of the nonhuman or natural world. In order to identify the benefits of dispelling the human/nature conflict it is necessary to discuss the possible problems and implications of Cartesian dualism. Because the 53 Fox, Warwick. “The Deep Ecology – Ecofeminism Debate and Its Parallels.” Environmental Ethics Vol. 11 No. 1 (1989): 5-25. 32 cogito is the starting place for his philosophy Descartes has trouble maintaining an intrinsic relationship between mind and body. Descartes begins with the clear and distinct idea that “I am thinking.” He then concludes that the “thinking” belongs necessarily to the substance. Since the body is not the “thinking” part then one could conclude that the body is not essential to the human. As Fredrick Copleston states, “For if Descartes begins by saying that I am a substance the whole nature of which is to think, and if the body does not think and is not included in my clear and distinct idea of myself as a thinking thing, it would seem to follow that the body does not belong to my essence or nature.”54 Following from the substantial differentiation of mind/soul and body one can conclude that the human is made up of two separate parts: body and soul. One can further conclude with this separation of substances that the body becomes a vessel for the soul. But since the essential feature is the “thinking part” and the body does not have this quality then the material substance becomes inferior to the thinking or rational soul. This separation can lead to a “justified” subjugation of the physical body to the soul. Descartes highlighted the distinction of mind and body but did not emphasis the complete substantial difference between mind and body in an effort to maintain the unity of the human person. The distinction between mind and body is not a problem, however, a certain interpretation of Descartes’ thought leads to a substantial separation of the mind and body further causing a subjugation of the material body. While he may not be at fault this interpretation of the mind and body as completely distinct, with the body as lesser, this interpretation has become the popular interpretation of Cartesian philosophy and the one with which environmental philosophy takes issue. Descartes provides the catalyst for a dualist tension between reason and the empirical world, which further entails a dualistic tension between humanity and the rest of the nonhuman 54 Frederick Copleston, SJ., A History of Philosophy: Volume IV Modern Philosophy: Descartes to Leibniz, New York: Image Books, 1963. 33 world. Because of the substantial difference of mind and body humans are “set apart” from or outside of the rest of the nonhuman world in a divisive manner.55 As Christopher J. Preston states, “Dualisms between culture and nature, reason and emotion, male and female, universal and particular, human and animal, have become mutually, enfolded and reinforcing of each other. But there is one dualism in particular . . . central to the creation of all others… the dualism between reason and nature.”56 Both ecofeminism and deep ecology at the centre seek to dispel this dualistic tension. Although, as seen above, ecofeminism proposes the division is an androcentric one, with women included in the segregated side with the rest of the nonhuman, non-male, non-rational population. While social ecologists would argue against the plausibility of deep ecology, they too seek to dispel the dualistic division between humanity and nature.57 William Cronon in response to the “wilderness” movement articulates the central problem with this dualism as follows, “this, then, is the central paradox: wilderness embodies a dualistic vision in which the human is entirely outside the natural. If we allow ourselves to believe that nature, to be true, must also be wild, then our very presence in nature represents its fall.”58 While Cronon is specifically referring to the American conversation of the preservation of the wilderness inspired by Henry David Thoreau, Ralph Waldo Emerson, John Muir, and the like, as they are working within the Modern philosophical context, the same criticism can be applied to the relationship of humanity to nature 55 Though it must be noted that some argue that this dualistic view of reason as distinct from the natural or mind as distinct from the body is beneficial to some theological or religious or even some common sense perceptions of how we think. However, this is not what is at issue in the environmental debate and thus the possible benefits to various worldviews will not be discussed. For a brief yet comprehensive discussion on the value of mind/body dualism see, Elliot Sober, Core Issues in Philosophy, Pearson, 2012. 56 Christopher J Preston, Grounding Knowledge: Environmental Philosophy, Epistemology, and Place, London: The University of Georgia Press, 2003, 112-113. 57 The social ecologists would argue that they attribute more significance to the human species, not undercutting the value of rationality, whilst maintaining that reason is something completely “natural.” 58 William Cronon, “The Trouble with Wilderness; or, Getting Back to the Wrong Nature,” Uncommon Ground: Rethinking the Human Place in Nature, New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 1995, 69-90, 79. 34 generally speaking.59 The radical ecology movement, with its emphasis on the inherent value of nonhuman life, regardless of use, as well as the insistence upon the wellbeing of the whole or the cosmic identity, underscores the importance of a dispelling this division of humanity with nature and further allows for this dismissal to be done. A significant benefit of the Radical Ecology movement – one which also makes it very difficult to pin down for the very reason that it is beneficial is that it promotes the sacralising or re-enchanting of nature (a reason for which Murray Bookchin criticizes deep ecology). The mechanistic view of the natural world that comes from the Enlightenment – through the coupling of Cartesian and Baconian thought – that the nonhuman can be understood through a reductionist dissection is certainly a significant player in the justification of the exploitation of the nonrational world. In his controversial and influential article “The Historical Roots of our Ecological Crisis,” Lynn White Jr. attributes this mechanistic reductionism to the dualistic division from the Judeo-Christian worldview.60 While one could argue Judeo-Christianity is not the source of the conflict, but rather a specific interpretation of Judeo-Christianity, his observation and assertion that the Enlightenment and specifically Cartesian philosophy is born out of that tradition, is astute and does provide a plausible cause for much of the ecological crisis.61 As discussed above, this Cartesian dualism and the philosophical conversations in response to it do champion 59 Although putting John Muir firmly in this tradition is contentious, as some would argue, as Bill Devall does, that Muir was the “first deep ecologist,” see: Bill Devall, “John Muir as Deep Ecologist,” Environmental Review: KER 6, no. 1, (1982): 63-86, 66. Oxford University Press on behalf of Forest History Society and American Society for Environmental History. http:www.jstor.org/stable/3984050. Accessed: April 3, 2017. I would agree that Muir does not sit firmly in the transcendental tradition but neither does he “fit” the deep ecologist mold either. 60 Lynn White Jr., “The Historical Roots of Our Ecological Crisis, Science, New Series, vol. 155, no. 3767 (March 10, 1967), pp. 1203-1207. Published by American Association for the Advancement of Science, URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1720120. Accessed: 10-11-2016. 61 It might be more accurate for Lynn White Jr to say a particular, historically situated, strand of Christianity lead to the viewing of natural world in this divisive manner. For a brief yet compelling defense of the benefit of Christianity (highlighting the importance of the Incarnation) see Wendell Berry, “Christianity and the Survival of Creation,” Cross Currents,” Summer 93, Vol. 43 Issue 2, p149, 15p. http://www.crosscurrents.org/berry.htm. Accessed on April 20, 2017. 35 Descartes’ “reason verses the empirical” or “humanity verses the nonhuman world” dualistic tension. As Michael Polanyi states, “the conception of animals as machines goes back to Descartes.”62 Carolyn Merchant provides a vivid analogy of the transition to a mechanistic worldview through her description of the transition of responsibility of childbirth from midwives to (male) doctors’ use of metal forceps extracting the goods from and subsuming the contributing role of women. At this point, Merchant argues, women’s contributing roles in society were stolen and they became “producers” of good. Likewise, the Earth, seen as feminine, “mother,” became a “producer” viewed with an eye to how much she could produce – how much could be extracted – in a calculated and mechanistic manner. Within this mechanistic “use-value” view of the nonhuman world, any matter outside of the human itself (and some would argue that humanity itself) becomes no more than a commodity.63 It is difficult to ascribe inherent value beyond use. The radical ecology movement, through stressing the inherent value of all things or of the whole, overthrows this limiting mechanistic view which distils the nonhuman world to its basic parts. The “re-sacralizing” of the nonhuman world or the recognition of the unity of the all entails the upheaval of all pervasive Cartesian-Baconian mechanistic view of the natural world. I must note that this is not to reject a clinical understanding of the nonhuman but that there are beings that cannot simply be understood in that manner. The direct benefit, beyond the well-being of the whole worldly ecosystem, is that it accounts for an aspect of human knowing and experience that is commonly overlooked. In his 62 Michael Polanyi, The Study of Man, Oxford: Martino Publishing, 2014, 52. It must also be noted that this type of interpretation of Descartes is problematic but that is not necessarily the view that Descartes himself espoused. As Peter Harrison argues Descartes uses the machine metaphor as an analogy but did not intend it to be taken literally. See, Peter Harrison, “Descartes on Animals,” The Philosophical Quarterly (1950-), 42, no. 162 (1992): 219-227. Oxford University Press on behalf of the Scots Philosophical Association and the University of St. Andrews. Accessed June 6, 2017. www.jstor.org/stable/2220217. 63 Alasdair MacIntyre in After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2010, argues that within the current “managerial” system of business, that the human person cannot be seen as anything other than a producing object as the system itself entails that interpretation of humanity. 36 discussion of the thought of Muir, Devall states, “Muir’s intuition of unity influenced his epistemology […] it is difficult in our language even to describe that [connection of surroundings central to all life] sense.”64 This element of human knowing is perhaps more clearly articulated by what Michael Polanyi refers to as “tacit knowing.” In his discussion of tacit knowing, Polanyi states, “Speaking more generally, the belief that, since particulars are more tangible, their knowledge offers a true conception of things is fundamentally mistaken.”65 By claiming that we need to overcome or move beyond the mechanistic and dualistic way of knowing, radical ecology allows for the encounter with being that is quite often overlooked in our dissecting analysis. Polanyi uses the example of a piece of music to explain this concept of tacit knowing. While the knowledge of the individual is essential, if one tries to play a piece on the piano while focusing on each particular note, the unity of the piece is destroyed. He states, “ The word uttered again in its proper contest, the pianist’s fingers used again with his mind on his music, the features of a physiognomy and the details of a pattern glanced at once more from a distance: they all come to life and recover their meaning and their comprehensive relationship.”66 The radical ecology shift from androcentric/anthropocentric-use, dissecting mechanistic way of knowing opens up the sphere of knowledge for an experiential knowing of the unity of things; it allows for the legitimizing of other methods of knowing that are not limited to number or usevalue. It must be noted however, that this particular benefit is not to fall victim to the antievolutionary thinking of Teilhard de Chardin which, as Dennett describes is to deny, “the fundamental idea: that evolution is a mindless, purposeless, algorithmic process.”67 So while the 64 Bill Devall, “Muir as Deep Ecologist,” 66. Michael Polanyi, The Tacit Dimension, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009, 19. 66 Ibid, 19. 67 Daniel C. Dennett, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life, New York: Simon & Schuster Inc., 1996, 320. 65 37 “unity” or whole thinking allows for a different method or acknowledgement of knowing, this does not impose a mystical purposiveness on the earth’s ecosystems. 4. The Cost of the Radical Ecology Ethic to the Human Species The emphasis on the cosmic self or the unity, while it may allow for a method of knowing that goes beyond reductionism, appears naïve in its assertion that we can shift entirely from anthropocentrism. In his article on the compatibility of scientific and religious ways of knowing, Del Ratzsch in “Humanness in their Hearts: Where Science and Religion Fuse,” says, “In the human-cognitive case, we apparently have no abstraction-permitting contrast – all our experiences are human-mediated. And this humanness cannot be purged from science.”68 Likewise, Thomas Nagel, in “What is it like to be a bat?” says, the following, “It is difficult to understand what could be meant by the objective character of an experience, apart from the particular point of view form which its subject apprehends it. After all, what would be left of what it was like to be a bat if one removed the viewpoint of the bat?”69 Although Nagel is responding to reductionist theories of mind in this article, his point can be applied to the challenge of the radical ecologists. These quotations from Nagel and Ratzsch, both emphasize our inability to step outside of our own consciousness. An inability to do so on the individual and species levels alike; we can only experience and know in relation to who we are as particular members of the human species. Radical Ecology, particularly Deep Ecology, requires that we “think for the good of the whole,” not putting our human needs above those of the other members of the biotic community. However, since we are not able to step outside of our 68 Del Ratzsch, “Humanness in the Heart: Where Science and Religion Fuse,” The Believing Primate: Scientific, Philosophical, and Theological Reflections on the Origin of Religion, Edited by Jeffrey Schloss and Michael J. Murray, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010, 215-245, 228. 69 Thomas Nagel, “What it is like to be a bat?” The Philosophical Review LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974): 435-50, 43839. 38 subjectivity, thinking in a global manner is asking something of our species that we are incapable of doing. Even if we imagine that we are acting in the best interests of the whole it is still in relation to our specifically human way of knowing. The assertion to do otherwise, the request to think for the good of the entire ecosystem, excludes the possibility of thinking to a human scale, or more simply knowing as humans. Similarly, the emphasis on a “global” solution, in addition to undercutting the value of individuals, may simply not be practical. While radical ecology advocates for a reduction of the human population on a global scale, regardless of one’s position on the morality/feasibility of reducing the human population, the scale itself may be implausible. Once something is moved beyond the scale of our human knowing the level of knowledge and the significance of what can be lost – even without knowledge of it – can be vastly increased. As Roger Scruton states, “The more distant the legislature from the people the greater will be the distortion.”70 This statement is based simply on the recognition that we know those things which are in close proximity to us more than those that are far. Roger Scruton in his analysis of global attempts of ecological solutions gives the example of the gamekeeper verses animal rights activist. While the gamekeeper works within a knowledge base from being immersed in the land, “he must control foxes and badgers if he is to protect ground-nesting birds; plant cover if he is to retain pheasants and partridge; ensure berries in winter and corn and kale in summer; take action against scavengers, dog-walkers and so one.”71 The other, (not always of course) operates on a feeling or emotional, but without the key factor of risk and embodied knowing. So while the radical 70 Roger Scruton, How to Think Seriously About the Planet” The Case for an Environmental Conservatism, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012, 98. 71 Ibid, 113. 39 ecologist calls for the global “stabilization” of the human population, this type of solution overlooks a way of knowing that is essential to practical solutions.72 Likewise, this impractical “thinking for the whole” method undercuts the value of the individual. Kierkegaard, in explaining what he views as the danger of Hegelian philosophy states: No single individual (I mean no outstanding individual – in the sense of leadership and conceived according to the dialectical category of fate) will be able to arrest the abstract process of levelling, for it is negatively something higher, and the age of chivalry is gone. No society or association can arrest that abstract power, simply because an association is itself in the service of the levelling process.73 This passage beautifully articulates Kierkegaard’s concern that what is lost in the Hegelian dialectic. In the Hegelian self-realising historical dialectic, Kierkegaard argues that if each member is acting in the self-realisation of the whole in the unfolding of history then the individual qua individual is not valuable in its own right, but only in relation or for the bringing about of the whole. In proceeding for good of the whole the uniqueness of individuals is “leveled” in the name of the cosmic whole. Kierkegaard’s concern with Hegelian thought can be applied to the deep ecology exhortations as well. Deep ecology emphasises the necessity of 72 Additionally, I would agree with Bookchin in the criticism that the deep ecologist’s first response to reduce growing populations ends up being a eugenicist “justification” of the reduction of the developing world. Given that developing countries have the majority of growing populations and that the top priority in the practice of deep ecology is to stabilize or reduce the human population, it is essentially a “justification” of controlling the procreation of persons in the developing nations. 73 Kierkegaard, The Present Age: On the Death of Rebellion, Translated by Alexander Dru, New York: Harper Perennial, 2010, 28. 40 understanding our identity in a cosmic sense rather than understanding ourselves as individuals.74 Dismissing the identity of individuals diminishes the value of the individual as it attributes worth only in relation to the whole rather than for that being itself. Additionally, if the value of the individual members is diminished then it is difficult to see how this does not diminish the value of the whole. Guilherme argues that the above objection does not stand; the value of the individual is not diminished through receiving their identity only in light of the cosmic whole. He argues that each being ought to pursue its own interest and by doing so that each contributes to the interest of the collective. Maintaining that there is a connected unity of all things each being acting out of self-interest also contributes to the good of the whole. For example, the human being who is guided by reason will pursue the same goals as other human beings. Likewise, it is in the best interests of humans to encourage biodiversity within the whole ecosystem as the well-being of the whole contributes to the well-being of the human species.75 However, it is difficult to see how that manner of thinking is not appealing to anthropocentrism, which is exactly what radical ecology is trying to avoid. Because Guilherme’s response rests on an anthropocentric appeal it does not stand as a proper response to the objection that the “cosmic self” devalues the individual. The most troubling aspect of deep ecology in regards to humanity is that it requires that we deny our uniquely human attributes or properties. Coupled to this denial is a contradiction with the evolutionary theory. Firstly, it requires that we see our identity in a more cosmic sense, as discussed above. But what this means, as Bookchin points out, is that we deny the fact that 74 Fox, Warwick. “The Deep Ecology – Ecofeminism Debate and Its Parallels.” Environmental Ethics 11, no. 1 (1989): 5-25. 75 Guilherme, Alex. “Metaphysics as a Basis for Deep Ecology: An Enquiry into Spinoza’s System.” The Trumpeter, Vol. 27, No. 3. (2011): 60-78. 41 there is something significantly different about the human species. Notably, Alasdair MacIntyre argues that the ecophilosophical system belittles the dignity and potential of humans because it does not contain a concept of a human telos. MacIntyre, denounces a “rights” based morality entirely.76 Or rather, as Daniel Dennett discusses in Darwin’s Dangerous Idea, natural selection produced the marvel humanity. Bill Devall in a review of the long term goals of the deep ecology movement states, “To focus on the development of civility among the human species is not to inflate unduly the importance of humanity within the ecosystem of life on Earth; rather it is to recognize how dangerous the human race is to the viability of the Earth's ecosystem.”77 This passage and others of the like in many of the deep ecology writings reveal a logical inconsistency. The emphasis on the danger of the human species entails a uniqueness and even hierarchical understanding of the species. So while explicitly denying the uniqueness of the human species, the emphasis of the danger that we can cause entails a uniqueness to our species. Thus the underlying principles of radical ecology, particularly deep ecology can be summed up in following two statements: 1) the human species deserves no unique consideration because it is not any more significant than any other species; 2) the human species is unique in its ability to cause destruction to the rest of the nonhuman world and thus we must actively pursue methods of decreasing this uniquely dangerous species. Additionally, what is overlooked it that if the human species is not particularly special or unique or deserving extra consideration in this dismissal of hierarchical care as “speciesist,” then why should the species drastically reduce its numbers? One what grounds? As Daniel Dennett states, “If ‘doing what comes naturally’ meant doing what virtually all nonhuman species do, it 76 Noted in Sessions article as well. Bill Deval, “The Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement 1960-2000-A Review” Ethics & the Environment 6 No.1 (2001): 33. 77 42 would be hazardous to the health and well-being of us all.”78 The thinking of the wellbeing of the whole appears to conflict with certain evidence from an evolutionary standpoint. While it may benefit the “whole” to think in respect to how to preserve or conserve the wellbeing as a whole, the adaptive benefit of favouring one’s offspring or species may suggest otherwise. If humanity is no different or is given no consideration over other species, then how can we, as a species, be expected to act outside of adaptive benefits of natural selection? While, again, one could argue that it is in the best interest of the species as a whole to preserve the well-being of the planet (as I think it is) in order to maintain our species and for the potential good of the other species, this is an inherently anthropocentric appeal.79 One who is not a radical ecologist can argue with logical consistency that it is in the best interest of the human species that we reduce the population but the radical ecologist does not have this luxury. The underlying premise requires that we not act from human self-interest. David Waller, in “A Vegetarian Critique of Deep and Social Ecology” argues that rather than giving a solid argument for why we should kill as few animals as possible, deep ecology exploits our own feelings towards the animals, saying, “Its [deep ecology’s] proponents exploit our [emphasis added] sentiments toward animals in order to advance ecocentrism, but they refuse to address the qualities in animals that give rise to these feelings in us.80 While I do not agree with the thesis of his article, Waller’s point regarding the method to “preserving” animals is insightful. By appealing to our feelings in order to make the “case” for animals, this is an anthropocentric appeal – it is not a case for the animals for their own intrinsic worth. Likewise, it is rarely, as Waller continually points out, a case for the reduction of pain for 78 Daniel Dennett, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life, New York: Simon & Schuster Inc., 1996, 78. 79 This point that the arguments for the well-being of the whole planet should be preserved for the higher quality of life is anthropocentric is one made by Peter Singer as well in “The Environment.” In Practical Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. 80 David Waller, “A Vegetarian Critique of Deep and Social Ecology,” Ethics and the Environment no. 2, vol. 2, 1997, 187-197, 190. URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40338940. Accessed April 4, 2017. 43 the animals, but simply to how we feel towards other species with whom we are meant to identify.81 This appeal to our emotions is the epitome of anthropocentrism, the very thing that deep ecology is desperately trying to shift. The denial of this uniqueness also threatens the benefit of radical ecology of breaking the constructed dualistic division between humanity and nature. In failing to recognize the properties of the species, a double-layered construction appears – by denying or misrepresenting aspects of the uniqueness of the human species, a false perception is presented. In this false representation I think it creates a further distance of the human’s place relation to the rest of the non-human world. The double-constructed nature of the radical ecologist approach is clarified in the following quotation from Naess: “I am not saying that we should have preserved the primordial forest as a whole, but looking back we can imagine a development such that, let us say, one third was preserved as wilderness, one third as free nature with mixed communities, which leaves one third for cities, paved roads, etc.”82 This division necessarily excludes or compartmentalizes members of the biotic community, distinctly setting culture “outside” of the natural world. Which makes it difficult to see how this segregation is any different than what Cronon critiques the transcendentalists of doing. Thus, while it is a double-layered segregation, it seems to be little more than a human-constructed oversimplification of the human species. III. Conclusion While they claim to offer “radical” approaches to shifting the paradigm the radical ecologists’ “solutions,” as a whole, rely on the denial of the uniqueness of the human species, rather than a 81 While I agree with Waller’s critique regarding the appeal to our emotions, I do not think that appealing to the pain of the animal would necessary contribute to the “radical” part of radical ecology, as it is difficult to see how a reduction of pain for reduction’s sake is anything less than a version of Mill’s Utilitarianism. 82 Arne Naess, “Ecosophy, Population, and Free Nature,” pp.118 quoted in “Ecocentrism, Wilderness, and Global Ecosystem Protection,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, Toronto: Prentice Hall, 245-262, 256. 44 “radicalized” account of our place in the cosmos. However, this method of thinking does offer insightful and invaluable critiques of the historical and philosophical reasons for the current ecological crisis. Additionally it offers beneficial elements to our relationship with the nonhuman world, and interesting conceptual and philosophical experiments. However, the solution also rests on a logical inconsistency and denial of the human attributes of the human species. Thus, in order for the solutions (the primary one being the “stabilizing” of the human population) to the ecological crisis to be plausible and logically consistent, the underlying foundation must be readjusted with respect to the understanding of humanity. 45 Chapter 2: Biocentrism or Holistic Environmental Ethics I. The Problem with Anthropocentrism and the Need for a Biocentric Solution Biocentric environmental ethics works within existing ethical frameworks but seeks to extend the ethical community beyond that of the human species alone. As Callicott states, “it may be understood to be an application of well-established conventional philosophical categories to emergent practical environmental problems. On the other hand, it may be understood to be an exploration of alternative moral and even metaphysical principles, forced upon philosophy by the magnitude and recalcitrance of these problems.”83 Biocentric environmental ethics identifies anthropocentrism as the root cause of the environmental crisis but seeks to work towards a solution within existing ethical frameworks. This field endeavors to apply various existing ethical approaches to the rest of the nonhuman world. The biocentric environmental ethics, following the lead of Leopold, adhere to the Darwinian evolutionary theory as the foundation for ethics. While there are many different types of community-extending ethical approaches, this chapter will mainly deal with holistic biocentric ethics. However, I will briefly address individualistic approaches as well, to give clarity to the holistic approaches by means of contrast. A. Biocentric Holism 1. Aldo Leopold Aldo Leopold’s Sand Country Almanac is a seminal work in the field of environmental ethics. Whether in varying degrees of agreement or with harsh disagreement Leopold’s “Land Ethic” is an oft sited text. The “Land Ethic” is the section in which he most clearly states his conservation view and method, but there are passages throughout the entire text that portray the 83 J. Baird Callicott, “Non-Anthropocentric Value Theory and Environmental Ethics,” American Philosophical Quarterly vol. 21, no. 4, University of Illinois Press, October 1984, pp. 299-309, 299. JSTOR: www.jstor.org/stable/20014060. Accessed: 28 December 2016. 46 central ideas. Thus although, the his essay at the end of SCA, “Land Ethic,” is the most influential section, offering a practical approach to his environmental ethic, the work as a whole offers important insight into the ecological movement. As SAC is so influential within the community of environmental ethicists, it is worth touching on the main points within this work. The “Land Ethic” encourages a reinterpretation of the relationship of humanity with the rest of the natural world. There are many aspects of the “Land Ethic” that are important but two in particular stand out. First, Leopold naturalizes ethics. As he states, “The extension of ethics, so far studied only by philosophers, is actually a process in ecological evolution.”84 He re-grounds morality in the natural world. He argues from an evolutionary biological standpoint, while citing examples from history showing the evolution of human ethical attitudes or worldviews. He begins by referring to the hanging of slave girls by Odysseus upon Odysseus’ return from Troy. He argues that action, which would now be considered unjust, was considered justified, even moral behaviour, for a great warrior at the time. The reasons for which Leopold argues are because the slave girls were considered to be “outside” of the obligatory moral community. Since that time, we have extended the moral community to include all persons,85 as such we view Odysseus’ action as unjust and immoral. This change in attitude, Leopold argues shows that ethics evolve.86 Additionally, as the evolutionary theory suggests that humans have evolved the evolution of ethics is simply a natural process taking place within a natural species. Second, Leopold insists that our relationship with the natural world must shift from the view of nature as 84 Aldo Leopold, “The Land Ethic” A Sand Country Almanac: With Essays on Conservation from Round River, (New York: Ballantine Books Inc., 1970), 237. 85 To ideally include all persons, for of course there are many heartbreaking and immoral acts e.g. genocide, serial killings, etc. However, these actions are usually considered by the majority as crimes, further proving Leopold’s point. 86 Although one could argue that the crime committed to Odysseus in his household was an act of treason, and thus it would be more accurate to claim that the punishment for the crime evolves but the action itself is still considered immoral e.g. disloyalty is still looked up with contempt. 47 “mechanistic other” to members of a biotic community. Individuals within the biotic community cannot be viewed solely with regards to their use to humans but must be encountered with respect as fellow members of the larger community. Although, Leopold insists upon the necessity of changing our view of nature as something of use to a community to which we belong, he still maintains some anthropic preferences. The following quotation cuts right to the heart of Leopold’s theory; “But we, who have lost our pigeons, mourn the loss. Had the funeral been ours, the pigeons would hardly have mourned us. In this fact […] lies objective evidence of our superiority over the beasts.”87 Implicit in this quotation is the difference between the human species and the other members of the biotic community. Although Leopold is typically interpreted as promoting the equal membership of all species in the community the fact that he notes that pigeons would not mourn is particularly telling. By noting the mourning element Leopold does not diminish the uniqueness of the human condition within the biotic community. Although we have to recognize the other members as members in order to know, love, and conserve, we must also not diminish the fact that it is only our species that does so. In doing so there is a justified preference of the human species over others in the biotic community. Even though he is frequently cited in environmental philosophical texts, Aldo Leopold is commonly understood as presenting a sentimental appeal for the need for a new approach to nature rather than contributing philosophically rigorous arguments.88 However, Michael P. Nelson argues that Leopold’s philosophical contribution is paradigm shifting, the full 87 Leopold, Aldo. A Sand Country Almanac” With Essays on Conservation from Round River. New York: Ballantine Books Inc., 1970, 117. For my own part, I would be inclined to use the word “difference” rather than “superiority.” 88 Notice the above example of “mourning the loss” of the pigeon in Leopold’s appeal to the immorality of needlessly eradicating another species. 48 implications of which are only now, starting to be understood. Nelson explains that Leopold argued that until conservation explored more philosophically significant and deep-probing questions regarding human existence and our relationship with nature, that it would not make appropriate headway. By arguing that ethics do not exist in a vacuum, Nelson claims that our worldviews influence and “justifies” our actions. As long as society maintains the Modern mechanistic worldview, humanity can justify using natural resources and will not mourn the loss of a species. Leopold, with the aid of ecology, insists on the need for a new attitude towards nature, which understands humanity as a part of the biotic community as a whole. Thus nonhuman species are worthy of our respect for their own sake. The insistence of Leopold on the necessity of changing the attitude of the relationship between humanity and nature allows for the birth of the discipline of environmental ethics prior to which had not been possible. Not only does Leopold contribute to the field of environmental ethics as a discipline but calls for a reinterpretation of how we view humanity as a whole. Nelson argues that it is not that Leopold did not make philosophical contributions through his Land Ethic but that the philosophical contributions were so paradigm shifting that we are just now starting to understand the full implication of his contributions.89 Additionally, a common criticism of Leopold is that his “Land Ethic” is a fascist creed that “justifies” mistreatment of individuals. However, Nelson also defends Aldo Leopold’s “Land Ethic” and environmental holism in general, against the claim that they have fascist implications. He shows that environmental holism does not entail fascism. The arguments against an holistic approach to environmental ethics is as follows. The practical implications of an ethical theory that is primarily concerned with the well-being of the whole necessarily 89 Nelson, Michael P. “Aldo Leopold, Environmental Ethics, and the Land Ethic.” Wildlife Society Bulletin (1973-2006) Vol. 26, No. 4 (1998) 741-744. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3783545. 49 excludes concern for the individual. Thus, the individual, including individual human beings, can be “justifiably” sacrificed for the greater good of the whole. Since Leopold argues that we must have concern for the well-being of the biotic community as a whole, his critics argue, he must necessarily overlook the well-being of the individuals within the biotic community. Furthermore, Nelson argues, the fascist argument, originated by Tom Regan, is not dissipated any, by the defenders of Leopold’s position (Callicott, Abbey, and Hardin) who encourage the good of the whole through the sacrifice of individuals, with statements such as, “I’m a humanist; I’d rather kill a man than a snake” (Abbey). However, Nelson argues that Leopold provides the evidence to show that he does not intend his “Land Ethic” to justify environmental fascism, nor does it entail it. He argues that Leopold’s focus on the holistic approach is actually a form of concern for the individual, as Nelson states, “we should protect and defend the whole because doing so would better insure individual survival.”90 Since the argument for a holistic approach is built upon the desire to better care for the individuals within it, Nelson argues that holistic approaches do not necessarily entail fascism. If there is any “ism” that can be applied to a holistic approach to environmentalism, it is communitarianism, as it emphasises the responsibility the individual has to the whole community rather than the subjugation or sacrifice of the individual for the good of the whole. Perhaps the best method of summarizing Leopold’s thought is to end with his own maxim: “A thing is right when it tends to preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the biotic community. It is wrong when it tends otherwise.”91 2. J. Baird Callicott 90 Michael P. Nelson, “Holists and Fascists and Paper Tigers…Oh My!” Ethics and the Environment Vol. 1 No. 2 (1996), 103-117. http://www.jstor.org/stable/27766017, 108. 91 Leopold, Aldo. A Sand Country Almanac” With Essays on Conservation from Round River. New York: Ballantine Books Inc., 1970, 117. 50 J. Baird Callicott must be considered both for his own thought and for his explication of the thought of Aldo Leopold, for he has made important contributions to both, and they inform each other. In “Do Deconstructive Ecology and Sociobiology Undermine Leopold’s Land Ethic?” Callicott provides a paraphrasing of Leopold’s maxim: “A thing is right when it tends to disturb the biotic community only at normal spatial and temporal scales. It is wrong when it tends otherwise.”92 While, he acknowledges the criticism of Tom Birch and Holmes Rolston, III that this maxim is incomplete and requires some nuancing, Callicott argues that it is in the nature of pithy maxims that they be incomplete and require further explanation. Thus it is a good place to begin in understanding his thought. There are many assumptions entailed by this statement: 1) humanity is a part of the natural world, having evolved through natural selection, and thus the things that we do, inclusive of culture, are natural; 2) as actions that we perform and the culture that we build are natural they are therefore moral pursuits; 3) species extinction, is also a natural aspect of natural selection; 4) The main issue and thus the main immoral action of the human species within the biotic community, is not that we are causing other species to go extinct (see premise 3), but the scale and speed at which we are causing these extinctions. These assumptions will be explained in further detail below. In “The Conceptual Foundations of ‘The Land Ethic,’” Callicott argues that, contrary to the popular opinion of environmental philosophers, Leopold’s “Land Ethic” is not a work to be taken lightly nor with a tone of derision. The reason that it is too often chided by philosophers is 92 J. Baird Callicott, “Do Deconstructive Ecology and Sociobiology Undermine Leopold’s Land Ethic?” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, Edited Michael Zimmerman, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1998, 145-164, 160. 51 because the philosophy within is too, “abbreviated, unfamiliar, and radical.”93 Callicott examines and defends the rigorous underlying philosophical arguments in the “Land Ethic” in “The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic.” He argues that the “Land Ethic” rests on three scientific principles: Copernican astronomy as the backdrop for ecological and evolutionary theory. Evolutionary theory provides a link of “kinship” between humans and other species, while, ecology lends a sense of community and social integration between all members of the biotic community. Copernican astronomy, “scales the Earth down to something like a cozy island paradise in a desert ocean.”94 From these three tenets of scientific thought, Leopold presents a holistic rather than individualistic notion of morality. Callicott argues that “The Land Ethic” is a deontological rather than a prudential ethic; we are duty bound to consider the wellbeing of the entire biotic community, says Leopold. Notably, Callicott emphasizes the somewhat paradoxical nature of Leopold’s ethic; nature is not amoral.95 Because of the evolutionary theory underlying Leopold’s ethic which requires us to see ourselves, humanity, as a member of the community of the living inclusive of soil, birds, mammals, etc. this means that we are a part of nature and thus, significantly, humans as moral beings are a result of the evolutionary process. An issue which Darwin grappled with as Callicott explains: Human survival and reproductive success, Darwin argued, grappling with this conundrum [the apparent increase of ethical behaviour rather than the increase of selfish behaviour], is only possible in a social setting. . . . In short, if there is no ethics, there 93 Callicott, J. Baird. “The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic.” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology. Edited by Michael E. Zimmerman, New Jersey: Simon & Schuster, 1993, 102. 94 Ibid, 108. 95 Ibid, 119. 52 is no community; if there is no community, there is no survival (and, more importantly, no reproduction).96 Or as Callicott states regarding “The Land Ethic,” “The biosocial analysis of human moral behavior, in which the land ethic is grounded, is designed precisely to show that in fact intelligent moral behaviour is natural behaviour. Hence, we are moral beings not in spite of, but in accordance with, nature.”97 The emphasis of nature as moral and consistent with Darwinian evolution is perhaps the most significant part of the Callicott’s analysis of ‘The Land Ethic.’ However, the “naturalizing” of morality is not without problems and there are important tasks at hand as a result. The most important task for environmental ethics, Callicott argues, is a philosophically justifiable non-anthropocentric value theory. Without a non-anthropocentric justification of environmental ethics the whole movement collapses in on itself and must resort to normative ethics. Callicott discusses theism, holism, and sentimentalism as three possible justifications for a non-anthropocentric value theory. Most closely tied to the anthropocentric view of ethics is the hedonistic utilitarian argument. Callicott argues that it is inadequate as the basis for a nonanthropocentric theory of environmental ethics as it necessarily excludes all non-sentient beings. Furthermore, it excludes the biosphere itself, as it is also insentient. Thus ethical hedonism must be rejected. Similarly, the theistic argument must be dismissed as, although it appears to sidestep the anthropocentric criticism by appealing to God, it is “essentially mythic, ambiguous, and inconsistent with modern science.”98 Likewise, the holistic argument that appeals to a Platonic 96 Ibid. J Baird Callicott, “The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic,” In Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology edited by Michael E. Zimmerman, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 101-123, 1993, 119. 98 J. Baird Callicott, “Non-Anthropocentric Value Theory and Environmental Ethics.” American Philosophy Quarterly Vol. 21, No. 4. (1984): 299-309. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20014060, 302. 97 53 existence of “objective good” fails as justification for a non-anthropocentric theory. The problem that Callicott identifies with the holistic argument is that is provides no justification for why the good in itself should be valued; every attempt to do so ends up appealing to an anthropocentric concern. The non-anthropocentric value system must be able to account for the following: An adequate value theory for non-anthropocentric environmental ethics must provide for the intrinsic value of both individual organisms and a hierarchy of superorganismic entities – populations, species, biocoenoses, biomes, and the biosphere. It should provide differential intrinsic value for wild and domestic organisms and species. It must be conceptually concordant with modern evolutionary and ecological biology. And it must provide for the intrinsic value of our present ecosystem, its component parts and complement of species, not equal value for any ecosystem.99 Conversely, Callicott argues that the moral sentient arguments are, by definition, “otheroriented,” and thus can form the basis for a non-anthropocentric value theory, accounting for all of the above. The Humean ethic is intrinsically “other-oriented” and as such it is nonanthropocentric, however, it is still human. As Callicott states, “the Darwin-Leopold environmental ethics, grounded in the axiology of Hume, is genuinely and straightforwardly nonanthropocentric, since it provides for the intrinsic value of non-human natural entities.”100 Callicott argues that we are genetically disposed to regard the earth and those within as part of 99 Ibid, 304. Ibid, 305. 100 54 our tribe, genetically disposed to value and find community with the other species of the earth. However, it is a specifically human system, as we are “doing” the valuing. Strikingly, Callicott argues, “Since normal ethical theory is conventionally anthropocentric, no critical theoretical thinking needs to be done. Environmental ethics is thus reduced more or less to cost-benefit analyses and public policy considerations.”101 Callicott makes the important point that, “a new, revolutionary moral paradigm is no more created ex nihilo than a new, revolutionary scientific paradigm. Without some historical continuity, a new theory, natural or moral, could not be recognized as such.”102 This point both highlights his reasons for founding his ethics on Hume and simultaneously takes a shot at radical ecology. 3. Holmes Rolston, III Holmes Rolston, III, in “Challenges in Environmental Ethics,” articulates that the central challenge of environmental ethics is the “attempt to redefine the boundaries of ethical obligations.” Similarly, in his lecture “The Ethical Imperatives of Wilderness,” Rolston states, “The question is, are we apart from or a part of wilderness?”103 He argues that life, inclusive of humans, sets up boundaries. So, what does this mean? How do we understand and reconcile human actions with the rest of the nonhuman realm? How are we to view culture; is it a part of the wild or an imposition upon it? How do we act morally towards those “outside” of our human culture? Rolston argues that the “is” and the “ought” are not so far apart after all. Or as he says it in “The Ethical Obligations of Wilderness,” seeing the natural beauty of American wilderness makes it easy to move from “is” to “ought.”104 However even with our environmental awareness 101 J. Baird Callicott, “Non-Anthropocentric Value Theory and Environmental Ethics,” 299. Ibid, 300. 103 Holmes Rolston III, “The Ethical Imperatives of Wilderness,” https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Ptq8BS91fko. Time: 8:48. Accessed: May 12, 2017. 104 Ibid, time: 15:32. 102 55 we still employ a semi-anthropic ethic which extends moral value to sheep and wales which implores us to act “humanely” towards them. Rolston identifies the underlying problem: how do we treat wild animals ethically with ethics that are learned/developed in culture, not in the wild? As Rolston says, “there is no value without an evaluator. . . . Its esse is percipi.”105 However, Rolston argues that value only exists in community. Because of this, the problem with anthropocentric value is that it rests on the assumption that humans are the only members of the community. Even though earth and its non-human community cannot reflect or understand values, they can still “claim their care.” While value is justified through our understanding of what is a “humane” manner of acting, Rolston, argues that it is possible, nay necessary, to move beyond a strict anthropocentrism. Important to note: while ethics exist in community, Rolston does not favour “The Anthropocene.” Contrary to proponents of the Anthropocene, Holmes Rolston, III, in his article “The Anthropocene! Beyond the Natural?” argues that we need to deviate from the trajectory of a human cultivated planet and solve the human/ecological problem where it actually lies. As he states, “If our concern is for the poor in this new humanist excellence, then emphasize environmental justice, more equitable distribution of wealth between rich and poor on developed lands, rather than diminishing wild nature to benefit the poor. Solve the problem in the right place.”106 Furthermore, while advocates of the Anthropocene argue that “wild” nature does no longer exist and that the parks we create are equally as constructed as Disney Land. However, as Rolston queries, “Wilderness advocates may wonder if anyone who makes such a claim has ever 105 Rolston III, Holmes, “Challenges in Environmental Ethics,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology. General Editor Michael E. Zimmerman. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1998. 124-144, 141. 106 Holmes Rolston, III, “The Anthropocene! Beyond the Natural?,” The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics, New York: Oxford University Press, 2017, 70. 56 done a backcountry trek in Yellowstone or the Bob Marshall Wilderness.”107 Rolston agrees that humans are the dominant species and will continue to become increasingly dominating (for the time being). However, although we have a duty to each other within our human species, this dominating duty-bound species is not excluded from having ethical obligations to other species as well. Our obligation to others species is clearly articulated in his article “Ecology,” which discusses the field contained in the title. Rolston begins with a discussion of the meaning and evolution of the meaning of the term “ecology,” by showing the historical roots of the word itself and the way that ecology has evolved since it was first coined in 1866. Rolston then discusses the central tensions at the heart of ecology. The simple meaning of ecology is a science that studies organism-environment relations; a field which influences conversations in technology, science, philosophy, and ethics. Ecological ethics refers to “doing ethics” in light of what ecologist have found in their studies – encouraging humans to imitate the way ecologies function or considering ecosystems to be a foundational good to be valued and preserved. The environmental crisis refers to the assumed inherent value of ecosystems and the potential threat to them from pollution or otherwise. Thus ecology and ethics have teamed to encourage humans to live more sustainable lifestyles in harmony with nature. Main concepts in ecology rely on ecosystems. A term which Rolston defines as, “a succession of communities rejuvenated by disturbances, energy flow, niches and habitats, food chains and webs, carrying capacity, populations and survival rates, diversity, and stability.”108 Of central concern is the question of how much of human environmental policy can be drawn from ecology, from which are derived classical is/ought 107 Ibid. Holmes Rolston, III, “Ecology.” In Holbrook, J. Britt and Carl Mitchams, eds. Ethics, Science, Technology, and Engineering: A Global Resource, 2nd ed, Farmington Hills, MI: Macmillan Reference, USA. Cengage Learning, 2015, vol.2, 27-31, 29. 108 57 concerns of moving from fact to value. Ecologists and their philosophical and ethical disciples challenge the is/ought division by arguing that there are values in nature that humans ought to consider and care for. As Rolston says, “ecology invites human beings to open their eyes and to appreciate realities that are valuable in ways humans ought to respect.”109 Ecology, as a discipline, assumes Hume’s problem of fact/value conflict is not a legitimate concern because if the ecosystem has value then we ought to preserve it. Thus the field of ecology itself assumes an ethical creed that steps beyond Humean ethics. Furthermore, while, our ethics have a distinctly human interpretation to them, ecosystems have a value that extends beyond our ability to manipulate or maintain them. Additionally, while it may sound like an anthropocentric appeal, Rolston argues that we need to cultivate and allow for the urban, the rural, and the wild to flourish and that in denying any aspect we are stunting elements of our humanity. As he states: “the more we become dominantly Anthropocene, the more we shrink to become one-dimensional, we hope for healthy people on a healthy planet. Alas, as likely a future as any on our present trajectory is a warmer, less biodiverse planet – weedier, more degraded, less sustainable, with a widening gap between rich and poor, with lives that are more artifacted, more artificial. We cannot be human without culture; that is our distinctive genius. Yet equally we do not want a denatured life on a denatured planet.”110 109 Ibid, 30. Holmes Rolston, III, “The Anthropocene! Beyond the Natural?,” The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics, New York: Oxford University Press, 2017, 70-71. 110 58 Additionally, Rolston points out that it is not that nature will cease to exist, but that we must quell our anti-ecological methods for our own sake. Nature will continue to exist long after the Anthropocene can thrive. As he states, “Nature has not ended and never will [. . .] wilderness will return to take what course it may. This ought not to serve as an excuse to continue our dominance; rather it should sober us into finding a more lasting fitness for humans on Earth.”111 Rolston adheres to a Darwinian model for the foundation of his appeal to the inherent value and adaptivity of ecosystems. Or as Christopher J. Preston in Grounding Knowledge: Environment, Philosophy, Epistemology, and Place, explains that, “Rolston moves towards intrinsic and systemic values by arguing that in all cases people find nature value-able only because nature is something that is able-to-carry-value.”112 4. Paul Taylor Taylor contrasts his life-centred ethics to the anthropocentric theory of ethics. He argues that we have a prima facie moral obligation to other life-forms such as plants and other animals themselves as members of the biotic community. In order to do so we have to reorder our understanding of the moral universe. Underlying Taylor’s attitude of respect for nature is a biocentric outlook of nature. The biocentric approach to nature is made up of the following four components: 1) humans are thought of as members of the earth’s community of life, holding that membership is on the same terms and applies to all the nonhuman members; 2) the earth’s natural ecosystems as a totality is seen as a complex interconnected web; 3) each individual organism is considered a teleological centre of life; 4) the claim that humans are superior to other 111 Ibid, 71. Christoper J. Preston, Grounding Knowledge: Environment, Philosophy, Epistemology, and Place, London: The University of Georgia Press, 2003, 115. 112 59 species if a groundless one and must be rejected in light of claims 1, 2, & 3.113 These four principles provide the base point from which we can start working towards resolving the environmental problems. They justify that we cannot proceed with a preference to our own species. Although, as Taylor admits, it will not be easy to place limits on human population and technology, it is within our power to do so and we are likewise duty-bound to try. Additionally, simply because it may be difficult to embody a respect for nature attitude this does not lesson the moral obligation to do so. B. Utilitarians Briefly Considered – Peter Singer and Tom Regan While the Utilitarians explicity state the framework that they are working from, they do provide insightful criticism for the holistic environmental ethics. In this chapter Singer examines and critiques two approaches to environmentalism. The first is the Western tradition grounded in Judeo and Aristotelian thought and integrated through the writings of Aquinas. This tradition, Singer argues, is anthropocentric and hierarchical and, although there are a few deviations, the dominant position is that humans have dominion over the natural world; a “right” given by God. Although this tradition can be harsh, it can still reveal a concern for the natural world. This can be done as long as the well-being of the natural-world contributes to human well-being i.e. the greenhouse effect could end up causing flooding in Nile delta possibly resulting in the loss of human life. Singer then asks whether we are morally obligated to extend ethics beyond sentient beings. Doing so comes with a host of difficulties. The first of which is that, without a conscious interest, we have no way of determining the weight that should be given to the flourishing of different life forms, as our value judgements usually come down to our own feelings. He similarly criticizes the deep ecology approach, as we have no way of knowing what it is like for 113 Taylor, Paul W. “The Ethics of Respect for Nature.” Environmental Ethics Vol. 3 No. 3 (1981): 197-218, 74-75. 60 a biosphere to flourish. As such it has failed so far in providing convincing arguments in that direction. Singer’s own view of what an environmental ethics should looks like in broad terms, “fosters consideration for the interests of all sentient creatures, including subsequent generations stretching in the far future.”114 On a practical level this ethic 1) discourages large families; 2) measures success not through the accumulation of material goods but through the development of abilities and achievements; 3) eliminates extravagant environmentally harmful activities i.e. unnecessary long drives for pleasure etc. Essential to this ethic is that we reassess our notions of extravagance and emphasize frugality and the simple life, not denying pleasure but finding pleasure in “warm” relationships and activities consistent with the environmental flourishing. II. Analysis A. What are the Operative Moral Frameworks of the Biocentric Environmental Ethics Movement 1. What must be Assumed to be True in Order for their Claims to be true? The fundamental assumption for biocentric environmental ethics is that Darwinian evolutionary theory provides an accurate and exhaustive picture of reality and thus that we are a product of natural selection. This assumption further entails that reason and morality are products of evolutionary adaptability. As such, the classical hierarchy of reason, will, passions, is a misrepresentation of the way that human ethics evolve or should be understood because our physical traits and adaptability defines or produces our moral inclinations and thus our ethical creeds.115 As Callicott states, “Hence, anthropogenic changes imposed on nature are no less 114 Singer, Peter. “The Environment.” Practical Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2 nd ed. 1993, 264288, 286. 115 This hierarchical classical approach to understanding the parts of the “soul” is originally introduced by Plato in Plato. The Republic. In The Dialogues of Plato in Four Volumes: Volume II. Translated by B. Jowett. London: Oxford University Press, 1964. 61 natural than any other. However, since Homo sapiens is a moral species, capable of ethical deliberation and conscientious choice, and evolutionary kinship and biotic community membership add a land ethic to our familiar social ethics, anthropogenic changes may be landethically evaluated.”116 Since our ethics are grounded in nature, another assumed truth is that nature is not amoral. Since these ethical guidelines are grounded in evolutionary adaptability as the foundation of ethics, this model provides the foundation for the ethical creed. As such, in the words of Aldo Leopold regarding ethical evolution, “[m]any historical events, hitherto explained solely in terms of human enterprise, were actually biotic, interactions between people and land. The characteristics of the land determined the facts quite as potently as the characteristics of the men who lived on it.”117 As J. Baird Callicott states in discussion of Leopold’s view of nature and morality; “The biosocial analysis of human moral behavior, in which the land ethic is grounded, is designed precisely to show that in fact intelligent moral behaviour is natural behaviour. Hence, we are moral beings not in spite of, but in accordance with, nature.”118 Thus “right” and moral actions and our knowledge of them are part of the natural process of the natural world. The emphasis on extending the moral community, like the radical ecology movement, is also critical of the over-simplistic mechanistic view of nature. As such, it also resists the dualist view of reality as the evolutionary story becomes the foundation and so places humanity firmly within the rest of the biotic community. The issues of this are described in detail in chapter one, 116 J. Baird Callicott, “Do Deconstructive Ecology and Socialbiology,” 158. Aldo Leopold, “The Land Ethic” A Sand Country Almanac: With Essays on Conservation from Round River, (New York: Ballantine Books Inc., 1970), 241. 118 J Baird Callicott, “The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, Michael E. Zimmerman, (New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1993, 101-123), 119. 117 62 so I will not go into detail regarding the problems of dualistic view of reality. While radical ecology works to dispel the dualistic tension through sacralising or mysticizing the nonhuman world, biocentric environmental ethics seeks to dispel this dualism through scientific evolutionary means. By grounding ethics, particularly environmental ethics in the evolutionary narrative, this dispels any lingering division between the human and natural world. Thus one can argue, as Rolston does, that urban, rural, and wild life are all needed for the wellbeing of three dimensional humanity. Callicott is right to point out that simply because our genes are selfish, this does not mean that we are selfish; to claim such is to commit the fallacy of composition.119 However, his method does provide a way of legitimizing a “favouring” of those closer to you which solves the problems of deep ecology, in some respects. “And, from the same cosmic point of view, we do in fact depend on our existence – with every breath we take, with every morsel of food we eat – on our fellow voyagers in the odyssey of evolution.”120 As discussed in chapter one (see pages 2324) there are issues with the scale of the radical ecology movement in its solutions that undercut or try to step outside of our subjectivity as humans. The emphasis of holistic environmental ethics on the adaptive benefits of morality allows for the preference or protection of one’s offspring and the importance of place in a manner which radical ecology does not.121 Resting on the notion of natural selection, the holistic environmental ethics framework first is legitimate in their claims that human actions are good, and second that even such results as the extinction of other species is not necessarily a bad thing. If humans and their ethical codes are a product of 119 Although, perhaps it is more accurate to say that our genes are persistent rather than selfish. J. Baird Callicott, “Do Deconstructive Ecology and Sociobiology Undermine Leopold’s Land Ethic?,” 154. 121 Of course, as argued by Callicott in “The Conceptual Foundation of the Land Ethic,” we are encouraged through Copernican astronomy to see the world as a “cozy home,” and thus care for the well-being of the whole, however this concern for the whole does not necessitate that we are not legitimately allowed to show preference for those in close proximity. 120 63 evolution and the natural world is not evil then the actions of humans must also be considered good in the same respect, when acting in accordance with the adaptive/evolutionary process. In this respect, holistic environmental ethics “solves” the underlying contradiction of the radical ecology movement. But further than this it is the acknowledgment that when we act within a natural human scale that our actions are moral, even if they do result in the loss of some other species’ lives in the building of homes, cities, farms, etc., thus showing that humans are part of the natural world. Additionally, the biocentric environmental ethic view does not entail a false dualistic us/them relationship between humans and the natural. As such it is consistent evolutionary picture of the world and as such consistent with science. As Callicott states, “Once again, it’s a question of scale. . . . The problem with anthropogenic perturbations – such as industrial forestry and agriculture, exurban development, drift net fishing, and such – is that they are far more frequent, widespread, and regularly occurring than are nonanthropogenic perturbations.”122 It is only the massive rate at which we are causing death and extinction of species and ecosystems that is at issue and thus immoral. B. What are the Implications and Possible Problems for the Biocentric Environmental Ethics Frameworks 1. The Benefit of the Biocentric Environmental Ethic to the Human Species What I consider to be the greatest benefit of the biocentric conversation, particularly Callicott’s contribution is the mentioning of the “scale” of the anthropogenic travesties. He makes a very important distinction between the actions of humans and the large scale, perhaps even beyond the human scale. Rolston makes a similar point with his emphasis on the necessity of the preservation of all types of landscape for the wellbeing of three dimensional persons. The 122 Ibid, 159. 64 holistic approach to environmental ethics emphasizes that the creation of culture and human changes to the landscape are not to be stopped or immoral: Rolston by arguing that all urban, rural, and wild landscapes are necessary for the three dimensional person and Callicott by saying that it is simply the scale at which we are changing the landscape which is the issue. The current rate of species extinction is bad.123 Rolston’s emphasis on the solving the problem where it lies, of actually helping the poor makes a similar and important point. The main “good” to be preserved is the natural scale sizes. Radical ecology, particularly deep ecology, tended to vilify human actions which resulted in contradictions, whereas the emphasis of the goodness of natural human scales, a scale that preserves natural scope of the species avoids the radical ecology altogether. 2. The Cost of the Biocentric Environmental Ethics and Internal Logical Issues The effort to ground environmental ethics in the Hume/Darwinian/Leopold model appears to work off of the evolutionary inductive method, however, there are some inherent problems contained within it. Firstly, the nature of induction is that it can only be proved false, thus as the bases for a theory of an ethical framework, it entails inconsistency. This eventually leads to a dogmatic claim for morality. Or if it is not, it is difficult to see how this type of ethics does not rest on dogmatism. The foundation must adhere to the principle that only logical certainty is that which can be falsified as falsifiability is the only certainty in the scientific method. However this model asserts that ethics is always evolving. This problem is discussed further below. In discussion of the “type” of ethic needed for a plausible environmental ethic, Callicott, discusses both Platonic conceptions of the “good” and Christian ethics. While, he admits that 123 J. Baird Callicott, “Deconstructive Ecology and Sociobiology,” 158. 65 they would solve the problem of a foundation for a non-anthropocentric environmental ethic, he ultimately dismisses both frameworks. The first, which he refers to as holistic “rationalism,” Callicott rejects because, although there is a standard of good it necessarily undermines the value of the individual;124 the latter because it is “outdated and anti-scientific.”125 However, the problem with dismissing any exterior appeal for the grounding of ethics is that the foundation for ethics becomes solely fact based, which ends up baring a striking resemblance to the ethics of Hume, indeed, Callicott explicitly appeals to Hume as the foundation for his ethics. Consider the following quotation from Hume’s An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, “Men are now cured of their passion for hypotheses and systems in natural philosophy, and will hearken to no arguments but those which are derived from experience. It is full time they should attempt a like reformation in all moral disquisitions; and reject every system of ethics, however subtle or ingenious, which is not founded on fact and observation.”126 This claim is essentially the same that Callicott makes in his rejection of classical appeals to or notions of “the good” and in his explanation of Leopold’s “Land Ethic.” Both the HEE and Hume use fact as the foundation of their ethical frameworks. While it is beneficial as it provides a parsimonious base framework that is consistent with an evolutionary view of reality, this model is not without its problems. The problems with Hume’s ethics and the holistic environmental ethics are made apparent by Kant’s criticism. In the “Introduction” to his Critique of Pure Reason Kant discusses the problem between synthetic and analytic propositions on which the Critique dwells for the remaining pages. In this introduction, Kant says the following about David Hume: 124 J. Baird Callicott, “Non-anthropocentric value systems, 303. The formulation in Platonic terms of the imitation of the imitation in the Republic. . 125 Although many philosophers would argue otherwise, that there is no conflict between religious belief and science and that there are rational explanations for religious belief. 126 David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, http://econfaculty.gmu.edu/klein/Assets/Hume_Morals.pdf, 6. 66 “David Hume came nearest to envisioning this [problem between synthetic and analytic], but still was very far from conceiving it with sufficient definitiveness and universality. . . . If we accept his conclusions, then all that we call metaphysics is a mere delusion whereby we fancy ourselves to have rational insight into what, in actual fact, is borrowed solely from experience, and under the influence of custom has taken the illusory semblance of necessity.127 This criticism of Hume by Kant, with nuances, can be applied to the Callicott/Leopold model as well. First, as stated above, the ethics in this model are said to be evolving (see example of Odysseus and the slave girls) and as such the claim is not for an objective morality as such. So one may try and argue that the objection does not stand as the moral code is not claiming any sort of “necessity.” However, there are problems with this type of reply and ultimately the criticism stands. The Callicott/Leopold model falls into the same error as the Logical Positivists with their “verification principle:” the same problem as David Hume. How can we infer the “ought” from the “is?” Their model entails logical incoherence in the statement of moral truths. For although Callicott appeals to the inherent goodness of the concern for “otherness” as the foundation for his ethics, there is no reason supplied for why being concerned for others is necessarily a good thing. While I agree, that concern for others’ wellbeing is a good thing, Callicott’s simple assertion that this notion is the foundation of his ethics does not make it necessarily good. 127 Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Pure Reason, Translated by Norman Kemp Smith, New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2007, 55. 67 The issue for the Callicott/Leopold model is that, while it may not perpetuate the fact/value distinction he argues that the facts are the foundation for the value; the “is” produces the “ought.” Consider the following argument from Callicott: Why therefore are anthropogenic clear cuts, beach developments, hydroelectric impoundments, and the like environmentally unethical? As such, they are not. Once again, it’s a question of scale. . . . The problem with anthropogenic perturbations – such as industrial forestry and agriculture, exurban development, drift net fishing, and such – is that they are far more frequent, widespread, and regularly occurring than are nonanthropogenic perturbations.128 In the above passage, Callicott definitively states that the problem with human changes to the landscape is that they are being done at an unprecedented large scale and that scale is immoral. While I happen to agree with him in the judgement in the immorality of the scale, his reasoning is problematic. This statement appeals to some sort of objective or external standard of truth. One can observably say that this type of action is unprecedented, but then to condemn it as immoral makes a judgment beyond what is observable. Presumably there are those who would disagree with that statement as well – those making profits off of this type of mass subjugation of the natural world for example – thus to call out their actions as immoral, one has to appeal to something other than the facts. However, Callicott already dismissed any notion of “goodness” beyond the working of natural selection as a legitimate appeal. One cannot begin with induction as the foundation or framework for ethics and end up with statements like “this action is 128 J. Baird Callicott, “Do Deconstructive Ecology and Social Biology Undermine Leopold’s Land Ethic?” From Animal Rights, 159. 68 immoral.” Again, while I agree with Callicott in many of his conclusions, it appears that the rational he uses in getting to them is little more than a dogmatic assertion that some actions are good and others are not. The above discussion of the Kantian critique of Hume in reference to criticism of Callicott is relevant for two reasons. First, Kant anachronistically provides legitimate and concerning objections to Callicott’s position. Second Rolston and Taylor’s position, where it differs from the Leopold/Callicott model, is built upon a Kantian framework, so the introduction of Kantian ethics helps to highlight the objections to Rolston/Taylor below. The Rolston model, while it follows some aspects of the Darwinian model adheres to a more Kantian duty ethic than an empirical adaptability model. Rolston, begins his article “Challenges in Environmental Ethics” by arguing that the “is” and “ought” are not so far away in the moral realm by appealing to a duty that we have as humans to act morally towards the rest of the biotic community. Rolston’s method or ethical framework is a duty based ethic. One cannot help but think of Kant when “duty” and “ethics” are coupled. Rolston appeals to the intrinsic value of all species as the duty to act morally towards the rest of the biotic community.129 One could argue that Kant makes the exact opposite appeal, especially as he begins his duty ethic in Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals with the following statement: “There is no possibility of thinking of anything at all in the world, or even out of it, which can be regarded as good without qualification, except a good will.”130 However, the method of justification for their respective duty ethics is strikingly similar. Consider the following statement from Kant, “all 129 Holmes Rolston, III, “Challenges in Environmental Ethics,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, Edited Michael Zimmerman, Second Edition, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1998, 124-144, 143. 130 Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysical of Morals with On a Supposed Right to Lie because of Philanthropic Concerns, Third Edition, Translated by James W. Ellington, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 7. 69 imperatives are expressed by an ought and thereby indicate the relation of an objective law of reason to a will that is not necessarily determined by this law because of its subjective constitution (the relation of necessitation).”131 The appeal to the “ought” is frequently made by both Kant and Rolston throughout their respective ethics. However, the similarity in method is made apparent through the following quotation from Kant: And just in this lies the paradox that merely the dignity of humanity as rational nature without any further end or advantage to be thereby gained – and hence respect for a mere idea – should yet serve as an inflexible precept for the will; and that just this very independence of maxims from all such incentives should constitute the sublimity of maxims and the worthiness of every rational subject to be a legislative member in the kingdom of ends, for otherwise he would have to be regarded as subject only to the natural law of his own needs.132 This lengthy quotation contains many key concepts for the justification of Kant’s ethic and undeniable similarities to Rolston’s Kantian environmental ethic, as well as some important differences. Explicitly, this passage states that Kant’s ethic is anti-consequentialist; regardless of the outcome, members of the rational community are owed respect, for simply being the type of being that they are.133 If the rational member is not owed respect then it may be treated as simply a means or something to be used like the natural non-human world. There are two very important things to note: 1) the intrinsic value and consequent duty that the members within have to act 131 Ibid, 24. Ibid, 43. 133 Note that “dignity” in the Grounding is often translated as “intrinsic value” as well: in text note in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/assets/pdfs/kant1785.pdf, 33. 132 70 morally to those members within that specific community; 2) Kant considers it morally permissible to “use” those who do not hold “rational membership.” Rolston appeals to the notion of intrinsic value as the justification for his environmental ethics. In his method of argument, the duty that we have to act morally is the same as Kant’s appeal. Consider: “we always shape our values in significant measure in accord with our notion of the kind of universe that we live in, and this drives our sense of duty.”134 What is excellent about Rolston, is that he, in some senses, obliterates the is/ought distinction, which is certainly a beneficial element to his moral theory. However, it is difficult to see what he is grounding his theory in, as he takes natural selection as the starting ground. Rolston, wishing to avoid the problem that the Leopold/Callicott model entails, through his appeal to the intrinsic value, appeals to a Kantian version of intrinsic value. Otherwise, he is left in the position of simply asserting that the natural world is good just because it is. Others would argue that a Kantian ethic provides a plausible and coherent foundation for environmental ethics. For example, John Martin Gillroy argues that Immanuel Kant provides an environmental ethic that contributes to the two separate debates within the current environmental ethic conversation. He argues that Kant’s theory of autonomy should be at the heart of environmental policy making as it defines the human duties to both nature and humanity through its focus on inherent worth. Likewise, the Kantian environmental ethic is comprehensive as it supports the conservation of resources for human perfection as well as promoting intrinsically valuable components of ecosystems.135 134 Holmes Rolston, III, “Challenges in Environmental Ethics,” 143. Gillroy, John Martin. “Kantian Ethics and Environmental Policy Argument: Autonomy, Ecosystem Integrity, and Our Duties to Nature.” Ethics and the Environment Vol. 3 No. 2. (1998) 131-155. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40338948. 135 71 While it is helpful to ground Rolston’s ethic in a classical framework, with all of the support that history offers, the problems or challenges that accompany Kantian ethics accompany Rolston’s method as well. As Alasdair MacIntyre states, “So ‘Keep your promises throughout your entire life except on’, ‘Persecute all those who old false religious beliefs’ and ‘Always eat mussels on Mondays in March’ will all pass Kant’s test, for all can be consistently universalized.”136 And, while eating mussels on Mondays actually sounds like a great addition to universal morality claims, it illustrates the inherent problems with a morality based on the categorical imperative; simply because we all may wish to make something a universal law, does necessitate that that law or wish is actually good. However, there is a far deeper problem with Kantian ethics as the foundation for a biocentric environmental ethic. Kant’s notion of the inherent value or worth of rational beings is our capacity for a priori reasoning. A priori knowledge provides the unifying concepts with which we understand the empirical world. Kant’s argument for the ability of reason to understand the empirical world is built upon the recognition that there is a fundamental difference between humans and the other species; reason is a faculty singular to humans that gives us the ability to understand the rest of the empirical world. As he states in the Critique: But the law of nature is just this, that nothing takes place without a cause sufficiently determined a priori. The proposition that no causality is possible save in accordance with laws of nature, when taken in unlimited universality, is therefore self-contradictory; and this cannot, therefore, be regarded as the sole kind of causality. . . . This is transcendental freedom, without which, even in the 136 Alasdair MacIntryre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, Third Edition, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2010, 46. 72 [ordinary] course of nature, the series of appearances on the side of the causes can never be complete.137 The very foundation for our ability to understand the natural world, on which his ethics is built, is that we, as rational creatures, are distinct from the rest of the natural world. Furthermore, although Kant does argue that morality must be lived, it cannot be known in any empirical manner. However, that claim goes against the foundational assumption of the environmental ethics worldview: humans have evolved through natural processes and are not distinct from the natural world. Biocentric environmental ethics seeks to dispel the distinction of humanity as the foundation for their ethics but this distinction is precisely what Kantian ethics is built upon.138 Thus an attempt to resolve the problems that come from a Humean ethic by shifting to a Kantian framework, still entail all of the potential issues with Kantian morality, but also bring more problems to the table. Extending the community in the Kantian ethics to include all of the biotic community either forces abilities on species that they do not have or entail us to necessarily exclude some species or existing elements of the biotic community from moral responsibility. Kantian ethics provides the reason for why we must act morally however, it rests on the distinctness of humanity. If we are to dismiss anthropocentrism and appeal to a biocentric foundation for ethics, the Kantian framework needs to establish a reason other than the capacity for reason to act morally. At the very least, it must give a reason not to treat nature as simply a means, as the justification for treating persons as members of the “kingdom of ends” rest on the notion of pure reason. While this may be possible, within a Kantian environmental ethic, such a 137 Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Pure Reason, Translated by Norman Kemp Smith, New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2007, 410. 138 It must be noted however that in his distinctions Kant is not implying that reality is dualistic; his distinctions are in relation to one reality. As he says in the Critique, “Taken together, the analogies thus declare that all appearances lie, and must lie, in one nature, because without this a priori unity no unity of experience, and therefore no determination of objects in it, would be possible.” Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Pure Reason, Translated by Norman Kemp Smith, New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2007, 237. 73 framework requires more nuance and thought to bring about an “ends” justification of the natural world. III. Conclusion The biocentric environmental ethics movements rest on the foundation of the Darwinian evolutionary theory. These ethical frameworks, working within existing ethical models, largely adhere to David Hume’s or Immanuel Kant’s moral theories. While there is certainly some elements of these theories that are beneficial to thinking about environmental issues shifting from anthropocentric moral theories to biocentric theories entail issues with these shifts, as many of the foundational reasons are inherently anthropocentric, and as such entail logical inconsistencies or at the very least problems that require further thought. Additionally, while I agree with many of the criticisms of current human actions and many of the conclusions put forward in these theories, the foundational logical structure requires shifting in order to stand up to rational scrutiny, particularly the Hume/Leopold/Callicott foundation as explained above. However, the emphasis of the goodness of the natural scale is a crucial point in the development of a plausible environmental ethic that must not be downplayed. 74 Chapter 3: Shifting the Moral Structure for the Environmental Ethics: Re-Thinking the Human Factor “Men did not love Rome because she was great. She was great because they had loved her.” - G.K. Chesterton. I. Should We Reconsider the Human Element? This chapter considers and adopts the ideas of four different thinkers and applies them to central concerns from left over from chapters 1 and 2. The thinkers in this section are not all environmental philosophers, however their ideas present possibilities for resolving the conflicts of the radical ecology and environmental ethics frameworks. While these writers discuss different topics from global economy to the scientific method to the history of the English countryside, the central theme that undergirds each of their texts is the focus on some aspect of the uniqueness and importance of the human species. It is not a dwelling on the human species as a method of dismissing the importance, intrinsic value, or beauty of other members of the biotic community, but an embrace of our species and the qualities we have in the recognition of our subjectivity that we cannot step outside. Thus in order to present a plausible and coherent environmental ethic, we must recognize humanity’s qualities and abilities: recall, the problems left over from Chapters One and Two were a result of too hasty a dismissal of the human species or of some of our attributes. A. Aldo Leopold Reconsidered with Notes from Berthold-Bond While Leopold is commonly lauded as articulating the necessity of a new interpretation of ethics to incorporate the “land ethic,” perhaps his most significant contribution is his emphasis on the necessity of humans to live in and love the land that should be maintained. This point is 75 commonly overlooked or dismissed as a naïve appeal to sentimentality;139 however, this sentimentality is of central importance and lends coherence to his theory in The Sand County Almanac as a whole. Of central importance is his distinction that we mourn the loss of a species. While the emphasis is often put on Leopold’s insistence of the extension of moral obligation to include the whole biotic community, his point that the human species is unique is commonly overlooked: an oversight that can cause the breakdown of his whole approach to a land ethic. There are many places through A Sand Country Almanac in which Leopold appeals to the human capacity of love. In reference to Leopold’s Sand Country Almanac, John Gatta says, “Leopold expressed the heartfelt sentiments of a distinctly defined personality who loved a certain plot of land in Wisconsin and could not live without knowing wild things.”140 He continues by saying, “developing a right relation to land meant enlarging one’s capacity to love. Stirring this impulse to love was, of course, crucial to Leopold’s rhetorical purpose in the Almanac.”141 Gatta’s emphasis on the importance of love as central to Leopold’s land ethic is accurate. For there are many times throughout that Leopold makes this appeal, as in the following quotation: For one species to mourn the death of another is a new thing under the sun. The Cro-Magnon who slew the last mammoth thought only of steaks. . . . But we, who have lost our pigeons, mourn the loss. Had the funeral been ours, the pigeons would hardly have 139 The criticism of Leopold as being overly sentimental is the one which Callicott addressed in his article “The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic,” as discussed in Chapter 2, in which he argue that there are strong philosophical arguments underpinning ‘The Land Ethic” and that it does not rest simply on sentimental affection. 140 John Gatta, Making Nature Sacred: Literature, Religion, and Environment in America from the Puritans to the Present, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004, 58. 141 Ibid, 58. 76 mourned us. In this fact [. . .] lies objective evidence of our superiority over the beasts.142 There are three essential things to note from this passage. First, Leopold emphasises our mourning of the loss because we love the pigeons. Second, entailed by this, working from the Darwinian model is the fact that we are in community, or to use Leopold’s term, “kinship” with the pigeons. Third, and what is most commonly overlooked, is that although, we are in community with the other species, Leopold does explicitly say that there is a natural hierarchy of species and places humanity, because of our unique ability to feel sadness over the loss of another species, at the top. Another telling story from SCA is from his chapter “Thinking Like a Mountain,” in which he recalls the shooting of the wolves for the “sake” of the deer. Upon encountering the dying wolf, Leopold says, “We reached the old wolf in time to watch a fierce green fire dying in her eyes. I realised then, and have known ever since, that there was something new to me in those eyes – something known only to her and the mountain.”143 Leopold continues to explain how that encounter with the wolf, dying by his own hand, changed how he viewed the ecology of the mountain. But what is essential is that it was an encounter of individuals – he needed to see the wolf and recognise the life slipping from her in a personal encounter in order to understand the significance of the useless death. In the abstract, he was happy to go about shooting wolves for the “sake” of the deer population. The personal interaction with the life of the wolf allowed Leopold to see and recognize the value of that life. While it is a love that is manifested through living in a place, thus creating a knowledge of the places that are to be preserved, it is a love that 142 Aldo Leopold, A Sand Country Almanac and Sketches Here and There, New York: Oxford University Press, 1968, 110. 143 Ibid, 130. 77 can only be developed through this knowledge and in knowing and living the love deepens – it is a natural growth of knowledge and affection. Of central importance to this appeal of love it that it is a personal love of places and species that is at the heart of the land ethics. It is a mutual giving and receiving of knowledge and love but can only be done within the bounds of our experience and personal interactions. Because of the personal love at the centre of this land ethic, the scale of the endeavor must remain to a human scale. As soon as the process or the framework exceeds our capacity to know on the human scale the proportions get lost and the nucleus of the land ethics gets shifted to the sidelines or lost in the renovation. However, when this happens, the logic of the land ethic, as the centre is off balance, becomes incoherent and the farther it exceeds the scale the more incoherent it becomes. At this juncture the appeal to human scale sounds like a quaint appeal but with little philosophical foundation, however, there are several key concepts from the thinkers examined below that provide philosophical clout to this claim. In “The Ethics of ‘Place’: Reflections on bioregionalism,” Berthold-Bond discusses bioregional theory with regards to aspects of Leopold’s SCA in order to establish a plausible foundation for environmental ethics. He argues that environmental ethics has become a “subversive philosophy of space.” Biocentric theories of environmental ethics, as opposed to anthropocentric ones, “dis-place” humans from their positions as the possessors of value and that we are just a part of a community of nature – a community which is inherently valuable as a whole.144 Since biocentric theories of environmental ethics are essentially about philosophies of place, bioregionalism is concerned with, “locating place more precisely and concretely.”145 As a 144 Daniel Berthold-Bond, “The Ethics of ‘Place’: Reflections on Bioregionalism,” Environmental Ethics, 22 (2000): 5-24, 10. 145 Ibid, 10. 78 theory, bioregionalism calls us to question the political systems that mask their pillaging of the environment and to “re-place” the politics of ecology. It is a call to “live in a place,” rather than to “live placelessly.” “Living-in-place,” although a call to nature, easily gets romanticized and can turn to a worship of the laws of nature or view nature as the guide. Essential to “living-inplace,” Berthold-Bond argues is the human element, the creative, meaning imposing, subjects who interact with nature to create a “place.”146 The subject is essential to the definition of place, and consequently bioregionalism, as it is the subject working within the natural context which creates the place initially. Berthold-Bond quotes Dodge, saying, “the very gut of bioregional thought is the integrity of natural systems and culture, with the function of culture being the mediation of the self and the ecosystem.”147 However quite often, Berthold-Bond argues theories can swing too far from the consideration of nature’s laws and look solely to the cultural aspect of place to define “living-in-place.” A method that is equally as problematic as it’s opposite.148 Finally, Berthold-Bond argues that the elusive nature of the definition of “place” or “region” within bioregionalism is because it is itself a relational structure; “it comes into being as a response of inhabitants to the landscape in which they dwell.”149 Because of the relational nature of regions, there can be no purely objective definition as places are never static. Place is never “finished,” as the response of inhabitants to the landscape can never be predicted. Place is therefore inherently vague, a, “quality without name,” as Berthold-Bond quotes Christopher Alexander. Although Berthold-Bond does criticize the romanticizing of nature in the theories of some bioregional literature, he argues, the spiritual nature that Leopold emphasizes in “Sketches” 146 Ibid, 15. (Dodge, 109, in Berthold-Bond 16). 148 Ibid, 16. 149 Ibid, 17. 147 79 is not necessarily a part of this romanticizing. Conversely, Berthold-Bond maintains that bioregionalists are interested in the spiritual redemption of the individuals through their connection/immersion in a place. Bioregionalism calls for a fundamental paradigm shift in the way in which we interact and view nature whose success is achieved through even one individual’s life becoming more fulfilled. In this manner, Berthold-Bond claims, Leopold is correct in emphasizing the spiritual component to one’s immersion in the land. By experiencing places, as a space of mystery, a place which cannot easily be understood, where there is “something to learn”; “he seeks to learn a different way . . . . where in order to know the marsh we objectify it and hence become blind to it, but by digging himself into it, by giving himself over to it. As such, he becomes transformed.”150 Therefore, the interaction of the person with place is not only essential to our understanding and definition of region or place, but also, our identity as persons becomes transformed through our interaction with places. It is a constant give and take by which places and persons exist in a condition of ever becoming through their relationship.151 B. Small is Beautiful: The Need for the Human Scale 1. E.F Schumacher E. F. Schumacher provides a thorough and convincing argument for the value and necessity of maintaining a human scale in order to establish a genuine and plausible economy. He begins his work Small is Beautiful with reference to a 1930 address by economist Lord Keynes which proposed that, “the day might not be far off when everybody would be rich” however, he cautioned that time is not yet, instead, “For at least another hundred years we must 150 Ibid, 24. This section also used in a comparative review of articles in “place theory” for PHIL 607 submitted to Myron A. Penner, December 15, 2016. 151 80 pretend to ourselves and to every one that fair is foul and foul is fair; precaution must be our gods for a little longer still. For only they can lead us out of the tunnel of economic necessity into daylight.”152 Keynes argues that in order for the world to be rid of poverty we must overturn morality and create wealth with no regard for the means by which we do so. Schumacher in Small is Beautiful argues against Keynes claiming it is not possible for a nation build on wealth to ever have enough. What is enough? Schumacher asks; “There are poor societies which have too little; but where is the rich society that says: ‘Halt! We have enough’? There is none.”153 Small is Beautiful shifts the focus of economics from concern over the amalgamation of wealth to a concern over the well-being of humanity as a whole and considers the philosophical approaches to ecology, politics, and economies that are necessary in order to do so. Schumacher’s chapter “Development” analyses the phenomenon of developing countries. The two largest sources of concern in developing nations, he argues, are mass unemployment and mass migration to cities. Many look at the problem and recognize the need, but then suggest that the solution lies in more aid.154 However, Schumacher argues that the root of the problem lies in the “dual” economy that exists in these countries; two completely distinct ways of life existing side by side. The humblest income of the “modern sector” consisting of roughly fifteen percent of the population far exceeds the possible income of the most diligent of the other eightyfive percent. The concept of evolution, Schumacher argues has influenced all areas of thought, except for development economics. In development economics we still think in terms of creation. Doing so, fixes the recipient of aid as a material object that can be “planned and 152 Schumacher, E. F. Small is Beautiful: Economics as if People Mattered. New York: Harper and Row, 1973, 22. Ibid, 23. 154 In the case of the deep ecologists, such as Naesse, Sessions, and Devall, the method of solving this problem is to decrease the population. 153 81 scheduled and purchased with money.”155 Undoubtedly, he argues, the problem lies with poverty. However, Schumacher argues that the level of poverty “degrades and stultifies the human person” and thus the problem cannot be fixed solely with goods. The real solution “starts with people and their education.”156 He argues that until we have concern for the person as the whole person and not simply for their material needs that the possibility of their economic growth will remain latent.157 Schumacher argues that in our excitement over our scientific and technological capability, we have built a system of production that, “ravishes nature and a type of society that mutilates man.”158 Commonly the solution is regarded as one of money; if we had more money, then we could solve the problems that we face. This system that we have built places the accumulation of wealth as the highest goal, the pursuit of which can “justify” any action. In regards, to the second development decade Schumacher states “[it] will be no better than those of the first unless there is a conscious and determined shift of emphasis from goods to people. Indeed, without such a shift the results of aid will become increasingly destructive.”159 Although he is speaking specifically towards the growth of economies in developing countries in this passage, this principle is applied to his theory through Small is Beautiful. Until the primary concern of our society shifts from the production and accumulation of wealth to the well-being of those dwelling within, we will continue to wreak havoc on and exploit the land and its more 155 Ibid, 138. Ibid, 140. 157 This passage sounds strikingly similar to the reasoning of Holmes Rolston, III for why the urban, rural, and wild landscapes must be preserved – for the well-being of the whole, three dimensional person – the person as a whole should be looked after, not just one element of his or her being. 158 Schumacher, E. F. Small is Beautiful: Economics as if People Mattered. New York: Harper and Row, 1973, 246. This claim of Schumacher’s is very similar to the problem that the Radical Ecologists and the Holistic Environmental Ethicists, are trying to fix as well – they are identifying the same problem, but with drastically different approaches to the solution. 159 Ibid, 160. 156 82 vulnerable members. Thus our society instead of being focused on the actual needs of humanity is built upon greed and the material wants of a few at the cost of the dignity, value, and humanity of the many. 2. Oliver Rackham & Robert MacFarlane Through his exploration of the history of the English countryside, Oliver Rackham raises some significant issues and key concepts to developing a plausible and practical environmental ethic. In The History of the Countryside, he states, “Tree-planting is not synonymous with conservation; it is an admission that conservation has failed.”160 At the beginning of the chapter, “Conservation,” from which this sentence is taken, Rackham explains that there are four types of losses that the landscape undergoes: 1) the loss of beauty, “especially that exquisite beauty of the small and complex and unexpected, of frog-orchids or sundews or dragonflies;”161 2) loss of freedom; 3) loss of historic vegetation; 4) and the loss about which he is the most concerned, the loss of meaning.162 Citing historical texts and the continuation of the countryside in France and other countries, Rackham argues that the cause of the loss of meaning and landscapes is not necessity or human need. Instead, Rackham argues that it is monetary gain and the “blight of tidiness” which result in the loss of landscapes. As the “meaning infusing” species, we have shifted the value of profits over meaning with regards to the countryside in the United Kingdom. Thus his point, in regards to the planting of trees being the failure of conservation, is the manifestation of money being valued over meaning and nature itself until we are driven to the point of this recognition and driven to the point of needing to re-plant: it emphasises the point that the land has already lost meaning. 160 Oliver Rackham, The History of the Countryside: The Class History of Britain’s Landscape, Flora, and Fauna, London: The Orion Publishing Group Ltd., 1988, 29. 161 Ibid, 25-26. 162 Ibid, 26. 83 In reference to the four losses that Rackham distinguished in his History of the Countryside, Robert MacFarlane says the following, “Oliver Rackham describes four ways in which ‘landscape is lost’ . . . . I admire the way that aesthetics, human experience, ecology and semantics are given parity in his list. Of these losses the last is hardest to measure. But it is clear that there is now less need to know in detail the terrains beyond our towns and cities, unless our relationships with them are in some way professionally or recreationally specialized.”163 By dwelling on the language of places, MacFarlane builds on Rackham’s expression of the loss of meaning of landscapes. The use of language, the naming of places, cultivates a knowledge and love of place that allows for the possibility of conservation. Macfarlane is not naïve in thinking that words will magically inspire or re-enchant a population to become naturalists, but, as he states, “Rather that they might offer a vocabulary which is ‘convivial’ as the philosopher Ivan Illich intended the word – meaning enriching of life, stimulating to the imagination and ‘encouraging creative relations between people, and people and nature’.”164 The emphasis on language, is the necessary first step in cultivating a harmonious relationship between humans and the nonhuman world and rests heavily on our ability to find meaning and gives names to the nonhuman places in which we dwell. In his anthologizing of place-terms, MacFarlane highlights the connection between the instilling of meaning and the affection we derive from the knowledge of places. The following quotation makes the point that it is not a homogenous “environment” that we are working to save but different and particular places and because of these different particulars it must be particular and individual loves – rather than a commitment to the preservation of “nature” while abusing the particular places, as he states, “For there is no single mountain language, but a range of 163 164 Robert MacFarlane, Landmarks, United Kingdom: Random House, 2015. Ibid, 9. 84 mountain languages; no one coastal language, but a fractal of coastal languages; no lone tree language, but a forest of tree languages.”165 This difference is also addressed in Rackham’s point on the deterioration of the English countryside. It is the meaning and the language as connected to the people living there who can instill and derive meaning from landscapes. Or as Macfarlane beautifully articulates, “To celebrate the lexis of landscape is not nostalgic, but urgent. . . . to defend what we love we need a particularizing language, for we love what we particularly know.’”166 3. P.B. Medawar & the Human Aspect of Induction As the evolutionary theory and the naturalization of ethics is the foundation of the morality and the basis for an environmental ethics in chapter 2, it is worth looking at P. B. Medawar’s The Uniqueness of the Individual, particularly his chapter “A Note on ‘The Scientific Method.’” Medawar argues that what is of great interest to scientists is that hypotheses get “devised” at all. He states, “Its creation is evidently a leap upstream of the flow of deductive inference. One does not, as writers of detective fiction stories seem to imagine, deduce hypotheses; quite the reverse, hypotheses are what we deduce things from.”167 He continues with the following, “The creation of an hypothesis is akin to, and just as obscure in origins as, any other creative act of the mind. If science were an art we should call it inspiration, but as only astronomy has a Muse that will not do.”168 Medawar argues that the hypothesis comes from a creative act of the mind – perhaps more formally called abduction – the crucial point is that scientific discovery rests, in a sense, on the human imagination or creativity. This is not to 165 Ibid, 11. Ibid, 11. 167 P. B. Medawar, The Uniqueness of the Individual, New York: Basic Books Inc., first printing 1957, a published domain book, 73. 168 Ibid 73-74. 166 85 suggest that we arbitrarily create the laws of nature but simply that there is a specifically human way of knowing that our scientific knowledge rests upon. Even though we have the capacity to abstract we cannot transcend our species and become what Firth argues as “ideal observers.”169 This idea will be discussed at some length before returning to Medawar’s ideas and contributions of scientific thought with reference to this paper. Peter van Inwagen argues, contrary to the ideas presented in Medawar that scientific know-ability rests on a human scale, that there is objective know ability in science distinct from any human subjectivity. Arguing specifically against the pragmatists, van Inwagen states that simply because a word is vague, this does not change the truth value of the concrete facts. He responds citing the height of Mount Everest as an example. Most would not contest that Mount Everest is 8,847.7 metres high. Neither can this fact be refuted by appealing to the relationship of tall to small things; there is concreteness to this number that has no bearing on any relationship. Furthermore it is in no way contingent on any type of human knowledge or human influence. As van Inwagen states; “If no human had ever evolved, and if no other intelligent beings inhabited the earth, the vast, slow collision of the Indian subcontinent with the continent of Asia, which is what caused […] the rise of the Himalayan Mountains [it] would have occurred in exactly the fashion that it did.”170 As there is no human influence and consequently no mind to refer relationship, this fact of the height of Mount Everest is an objective truth not subject to the relativity of human understanding and limitation. Thus by simply measuring the height of the mountain we can learn the objective, impersonal, fact about its height.171 169 Firth, Roderick. “Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, VIl. 12, No. 3 (March 1952), 317-345, 319 170 Van Inwagen, Peter. “Objectivity.” http://jeffsnapper.org/assets/vaninwagenobj.pdf, 528-529, 238. 171 Example used in Philosophy of Competing Paradigms paper, submitted December 31, 2015. 86 Empirical knowledge is not simply subject to our whim nor does this mean that it is completely relative but that we have human lenses through which we view the material world, which we cannot remove. Van Inwagen is correct in pointing out that since the evolution of humankind has had no influence (or as far as we can tell) on the collision of the subcontinents that we have no influence on the actual fact of the mountain. However, from this, he concludes that we can then know the objective, non-human-influenced, height of the mountain. This conclusion is too hasty and simply overlooks the human aspect to further conclude that it is not present. Metres are an efficient way to measure the height of the mountain; they are large enough that there is the possibility of encompassing the vast height of the mountain but small enough or to enough to a human scale that we can understand what a metre looks like and thus further grasp that over 8000 metres is quite large. Certainly Mount Everest is 8,847.7 metres high but what if it is measured in millimetres? Each millimetre unit is placed on each surface of the mountain measuring around each uneven surface or jutting edge of each stone. Measured this way the mountain would be much taller than 8000 metres once all of the millimetres were added together. Measuring Mount Everest with millimetres seems ridiculous, but it is only ridiculous because it so impractical to us. For an ant this may be a completely practical way of measuring the height of the mountain because this unit of measure is to the scale of the ant. Thus the relationship of the person to the objective size of the mountain is relevant. When measured in a specific way, using metres, the mountain is a specific height but what are the reasons that we use this specific method of measuring and this unit of height? The reasons for this method of measuring are because they are to our human scale. Our way of measuring has no bearing on the actual states of affairs of the mountain (although this is allowing that we overlook the fact that the human has to determine where the mountain is distinct from the rest of the land thus determining which point it 87 ought to be measured from) in this van Inwagen is correct but in terms of “objectively” knowing the height of the mountain we must accept that we know the height only in relation to how it pertains to us.172 We can objectively know the height of the mountain in metres but it is the relation of the metre to our human scale or size that measures the mountain in metres in the first place; we subjectively know that it is objectively true that Mount Everest is 8,847.7 metres. Similarly, Medawar argues that all of scientific inquiry rests on two pillars, which together form the “metatheory” without which reason cannot rest: logical syntax and semantics. As he states, “logical syntax, deals with the concepts of formal truth and falsity and the ordinances that govern the activity of deducing. . . . semantics, more recent origin and lay circles now more fashionable, deal with the theory of the meanings of words and the ideas of material truth and falsity.”173 This cooperation of the content and form of truth and falsity in the scientific endeavor does not underwrite the existence of facts or logical form outside of our understanding, but simply that since we are doing the understanding the content cannot be excluded from the form and the content comes with our human-infused preferences or ideas. 4. Wendell Berry Finally, Wendell Berry offers the concept of “affection” that is essential to the development of a plausible environmental ethic. In his lecture “It All Turns on Affection,” Wendell Berry makes the distinction between “stickers” and “boomers.” “Boomers” are those who want to exploit the land, with an eye only to monetary gain and after having done so, to live their lives work-free and wealthy, whereas, “Stickers on the contrary are motivated by affection, 172 Of course there may be benefits to knowing the height of the mountain in millimetres or various other unorthodox means of measurement but these too would gain their value through our human lense even if it is just because we would like to know how it is an ant would measure Mount Everest. 173 P.B. Medawar, “A Note on the Scientific Method,” The Uniqueness of the Individual, New York: Basic Book Publishers Inc., 74. 88 by such love for a place and its life that they want to preserve it and remain in it.”174 Driven by “boomers” the current economy ignores the land economy, in the interests of dollars and cents. The love of land and the well-being of the land is preserved only through the love of the “sticker.” As he states in reference to his family ties to their historical land, “if we had not lived there to be reminded and to remember, nobody would have remembered. If we, like most of our generation, had moved away, the place with its memories would have been lost to us and we to it. . . . I am fairly literally flesh of its flesh.”175 Berry emphasises the bond between himself and the land, acknowledging that he is made by the land – he is dependent upon it and it has become a part of him. However, this ability rests on the fact that he loves the land, a love cultivated through personal and experiential knowledge of it. A personal love that lives through the memory and the interaction between himself and the land, as he states: But the risk, I think, is only that affection is personal. If it is not personal, it is nothing; we don’t, at least, have to worry about governmental or corporate affection. And one of the endeavors of human cultures, from the beginning, has been to qualify and direct the influence of emotion. The word ‘affection’ and the terms of value that cluster around it – love, care, sympathy, mercy, forbearance, respect, reverence – have histories and meanings that raise the issue of worth. We should, as our culture has warned us over and over again, give our affection to things that are true, just, 174 Wendell Berry, “It All Turns on Affection,” It All Turns on Affection: The Jefferson Lecture and Other Essays, 11. 175 Ibid, 12. 89 and beautiful. When we give affection to things that are destructive, we are wrong.176 The personal love rests on our ability to show and experience love as persons (which admittedly sounds like a tautology), which further rests on the capacity to interact with those whom we love on a personal level – entailing a love within the human scale. To illustrate the importance of the human scale to personal love, Berry uses the example of the industrialization of the tobacco industry and its relationship with his grandfather. Berry explains that the industrialist James B. Duke, was a man who in his early years would have known those similar to Berry’s grandfather. In later years as the tobacco industry grew in size, the farmers, such as Berry’s grandfather, become removed and as such reduced to a mere statistic, or in Berry’s terms, as “negligible detail;” once seen in this regard, they could be dismissed or hurt with little or no concern. The size and distance caused by the industry removed any feeling of “community” or care from those persons and as such the land that was their heritage, home, and method of provision, could be used for monetary growth without a care to the loss of those dwelling therein. As Berry states, “Power deals ‘efficiently’ with quantities that affection cannot recognize.”177 However, as Berry argues, this size and the resulting power of industrialism, for industrialisms’ sake, rests on the notion that the land and the people can be “divorced without harm.”178 And furthermore in this divorce, that the human prospect can be brightened through subjugation and exploitation of the land for wealth’s sake. However, this is not the case, as Berry states, “But land abuse cannot brighten the human prospect. There is in fact no distinction between the fate of the land and the fate of the people. When one is abused, 176 Ibid, 15. Ibid, 16. 178 Ibid, 18. 177 90 the other suffers.”179 Resting on the notion that we are intrinsically connected to the land by trying to separate that connection and exploit the one ultimately ends up as a misuse and/or abuse of the other. However, this does not necessitate that all persons become farmers or should not have jobs in industries, offices, etc., simply that the exploitation of the land cannot be done without an exploitation of humanity as well. In our current age we are unwilling to accept the physical limitations of our species and endeavor to step outside the bounds of our physicality. As Berry states, “Now the two great aims of industrialism – replacement of people by technology and concentration of wealth into the hands of a small plutocracy – seem close to fulfillment.”180 These aims are the opposite of the foundations of nature and culture which are, according to Berry, “The fertility cycle turns by the law of nature. The cultural cycle turns on affection.”181 “In my region and within my memory, for example, human life has become less creaturely and more engineered, less familiar and more remote from local places, resources, pleasures, and associations. Our knowledge, in short, has become increasingly statistical.”182 Statistical knowledge is known by means of “facts” or “data.” This type of knowledge assumes an ownership or dominion over the knowledge, which is inherently problematic if we “know” our land solely in this manner. As he states, “Statistical knowledge is remote, and it isolates us in our remoteness.”183 As illustrated by the tale about his grandfather, this type of removed-knowing also allows us to inflict harm easily and without care, as it is already at a distance so removed that we cannot properly care. Berry further claims, “Propriety of scale in all human undertakings is paramount, and we ignore it. We are now betting 179 Ibid. Ibid, 22. 181 Ibid, 23. 182 Ibid, 23. 183 Ibid, 25. 180 91 our lives on quantities that far exceed all our powers of comprehension. . . . we are thus isolated within our uniquely human boundaries, which we certainly cannot transcend or escape by means of technological devices.”184 Berry uses the striking example of the effect on our hearts of the knowledge of many deaths in war, as opposed to the gravity of one death fully imagined. Citing it as a “horrible fact” that we can read in the paper of many deaths and destruction without breaking down – a thought that ought to terrify us – this ability to receive this knowledge with apparent apathy is because these facts have been removed beyond our scope of knowledge. He says, “The effort to connect cities with their surrounding rural landscapes rests exactly upon the recognition of human limits and the necessity of human scale.”185 The appropriate human scale breeds affection for the things within that sphere and it is this affection that is necessary in order to instill and develop a plausible environmental ethic. As Berry states, “Affection can teach us, and soon enough, if we grant appropriate standing to affection.”186 However, in order to have, cultivate, and receive affection, we must acknowledge our physical limits and reorient ourselves within a natural human scale. II. Re-adjusting the Moral Structures A. Re-adjustment to Radical Ecology As discussed in chapter one, one of the greatest contributions of the radical ecology movement is that it allows for the acknowledgement of the needs and existence of beings beyond their mechanistic parts. This aspect allows for the “sacralising” or re-enchanting of the natural world – resulting is a mystical-type language or experience; something which Aldo Leopold (and Christopher Alexander) refers to as “a quality without name.” Through the extension of the 184 Ibid, 25-26. Ibid, 31. 186 Ibid, 32. 185 92 ethical community to include all of the biotic community, they claim that the mechanising, usevaluing, of the nonhuman will be expunged. However, this action is primarily done through the “stabilizing” of the human population, a solution reached through the logically incoherent statement regarding the human species.187 Based on this claim Deep Ecologists conclude that the number of consumers must be reduced. The increasingly larger human population, as consumers, tends to use the nonhuman world for our own selfish needs and wants with little regard for the well-being of the nonhuman world. As the solution to the problem of the rampant consumerism by humans, their initial solution is to decrease the number of possible “consumers.” The radical ecologists are correct in identifying the birth of the problem and misuse of the natural world as stemming from the growth of the scientific revolution; the Baconian and Cartesian method of the reduction and analysis – in its extreme form and with only this view – does appear to “justify” a misuse. However, it is not that this is an anthropocentric “justification.” This method of viewing the world solely in these terms also strips dignity from the human species and reduces us to little more than “consumers” or” users.” It is not that the anthropocentric ethic causes the misuse of the nonhuman world, but that the interpretation or view of our species as users perpetuates that identity in our actions. In Small is Beautiful Schumacher acknowledges that the greatest problem with our economy is poverty. The developing countries, he argues, and indeed it would be generally acknowledged, struggle with the mass migration to cities, starvation, etc. While the central problem is poverty, it is not simply a lack of goods but a poverty of the whole person – inclusive of spiritual goods, education, physical health, etc. Thus the solution is not simply throwing material goods at the 187 Again, for “stabilizing” read “decreasing:” since the populations that are increasing are in developing countries, “stabilizing” is a soft term for preventing and controlling the births and lives of the world’s most poor and vulnerable. 93 poor in the developing countries. The criticism that Schumacher raises regarding “aid” is similar to the solution advocated by radical ecology. On a fundamental level, the radical ecology movement suggests that we remove the poor in order to “solve” the problem of poverty. They couch the removal in the softer language of “stabilizing” as it is a positive word conjuring imagery of building and strength and is certainly easier to swallow than a blunt appeal to eradicate any possible new consumers. While it is the consumer culture that is the problem the solution is not simply to remove possible consumers. This creates a twofold shift – it reaffirms our understanding of humans solely as consumers while not actually addressing the problem. Recall that this was part of the logical contradiction we were left with at the end of Chapter One. The radical ecology emphasis on a global solution to the environmental problems we face removes the issue from our hands and by its very scale prevents a plausible solution. As the problem is a global one, the radical ecology movement emphasized a solution on a global scale. Although perhaps laudable in its intent, this emphasis one a global solution perpetuates the distance and removes the issues from the sphere of human affection – a problem addressed by Berry above. By removing the solution from the human scale, not only does this remove the issue from our level and capacity of affection, it is also dismissal of our manner of knowing and our physicality. In doing so, it also removes contributions from certain members of society and thus becomes elitist.188 By turning our attention from the human characteristics in favour of a global way of thinking our form of action becomes ineffective. However, if we return to a legitimate way of human action with an embrace of the uniqueness of our species to reflect, to love, to know, then in doing so we return to the scale that will allow for plausible and positive changes. Furthermore, this type of action does not require that we not try and implement this 188 This is something Roger Scruton address How to Think Seriously About Our Planet, as well. 94 type of action and thinking on a global level, it is only the order which is reversed. We begin with a focus on the individual persons and societies and encourage this concern for individuals on a more global level. Applying the concepts from each of the thinkers above to our understanding of the human species, this can resolve the contradiction that the radical ecology espouses. We must first see the members of our own species as the creative, meaning imbuing, beings of affection that we are: that we cannot be reduced to our mechanistic parts and known only through our material consumption. Recall the logical contradiction we were left with at the end of Chapter One: the human species is not unique and must be given no special consideration over the rest of the biotic community and the human species is unique and can cause destruction on a level far surpassing any other member of the biotic community so this species alone must be actively stabilized with an eye to reduction. Reason does not allow for us to genuinely accept both of these propositions. Additionally, since the conversation about how we are causing environmental problems is a conversation that we are having the second proposition appears self-evidently true. However, the first part of the second proposition is only self-evident; it is not self-evident that the human species must be reduced, nor do I think it necessary. Once we accept that perhaps our species is unique, then only can we begin to ask “how?” in the hopes that we can use this uniqueness to aid our environmental pursuits. As the thinkers above, but particularly Leopold and Berry, argue we are unique in our ability to feel affection for all members of the biotic community. This ability rests on our human capacity to act within our human scale. Recall the example from Leopold and the shooting of the wolf. In short in order to recognize the other members of the biotic community as community members, we must first see those members of our own species as members of our community not 95 as individuals that can be sacrificed for the good of the whole.189 However this capability as argued by Berry, rests on our ability to act or think affectionately towards others. This further requires that we do not exceed our limitations in knowing and interactions for in doing so we do reduce humanity to consumers or degrade some aspect of our species. This degradation is excellently illustrated in Coleridge’s Ancient Mariner. The problem lies with our inability to find community with anyone, not just those outside our human community, as a result of the denial of some aspect of our species we do not find community with anyone, human or otherwise. It rests on an autonomous use-valuing of our human species, instead of a communitarian ethics. Instead of being anthropocentric the practice of this type of ethics might more accurately be described as solipsistic or self-centred. Coleridge’s anthropology offers insight into the problem and the central defining feature of humanity as our ability to love. As Christopher Dinkel states in reference to the Coleridge’s anthropology: “The mariner’s curse is brought about by his killing the albatross, and his salvation is initiated by his learning to love the sea-snakes that had so revolted him. . . . In the poem, the mariner forfeits his humanness in his senseless killing of the albatross. In effect, the mariner has become imbruted. The act of killing the albatross indicates the Mariner’s fragmented humanness. This loveless act moves the Mariner into a world devoid of love and even the 189 Perhaps it is possible to act ethically towards other species in the biotic community without recognizing the closeness of our own species, however, the way that this is presented by the radical ecologists is unconvincing and for my own part, I remain skeptical towards this possibility. 96 capacity to love. Whatever he had been before, he has further degraded whatever humanity he had.”190 This interpretation of Coleridge’s portrayal of the fall of the Mariner is analogous to the problem of the post-Enlightenment ethics showing the inability to recognize those with whom we are (or ought to be) in community with and encounter them with a genuine expression of care. The radical ecology movement suggests that we see other species and members of the biotic community as community. In doing so, however, they request that we see those closest to our community with less value; citing anthropocentrism as the root of the ecological crisis humans are “justifiably” condemned. However it is not that case that anthropocentrism is the cause of the problem. Indeed if the ethics “justifying” ecological abuse were actually anthropocentric, the poor, indeed all persons, would be of central concern as well. If this were the case, then the economy could not run on the exploitation of the poor or developing countries. If that were the case, then there would not be such an exploitation of the nonhuman world because, as Rolston argues we do need urban, rural, and wilderness landscapes for human well-being. It is the “justification” of exploitation that is the problem. The exploitation is not limited to nature or women or the nonhuman, but it includes an exploitation of all of the poor and of human nature in general. Our capacity for consumption and greed are great – these characteristics are exploited even by ourselves and the other elements of our beings over looked – thus “justifying” our actions as consumers and exploiters. The deep ecology movement offers invaluable insight into the encounter with others in the nonhuman community, emphasizing that beings are not reducible to their use value to 190 Christopher Dinkel, “Coleridge the Rime, and the Image of God: Humanness as Communion with Creator,” The Friends of Coleridge, New Series 34, Winter 2009, http://www.friendsofcoleridge.com/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=6&Itemid=29, 42-44. 97 humans but to be respected in their own right. While their criticism of human actions is astute, the radical ecology movement over-corrects and ends up reducing the value of the human species and rejecting the necessity of recognizing the closeness of our human community. It disregards the unique ability of our species to feel affection and moral responsibility to others. However, this ability is something that cannot be extended to the members of the biotic community unless we learn it first from members of our own species as it is a skill or habit developed and cultivated in relationship with persons, places, and other species. B. Re-adjustment to Holistic Environmental Ethics A similar shift in focus with regards to humanity is necessary for the holistic environmental ethics to be plausible as well. J. Baird Callicott insightfully describes the immorality of our human actions as the result of the scale of the widespread misuse, abuse, and subjugation of the other members of the biotic community. However, he then in turn, offers the Humean ethical creed as the solution. His criticism is astute and completely accurate however the solution perhaps does not get far enough to the heart of the issue. Callicott’s argument that the problem with human interference on the rest of the nonhuman world is the large scale with which it is done, that it is done on a scale that surpasses our natural human needs, however as the solution he dismisses the human scale in his correction and goes to the concepts of adaptability and natural selection for the source of the solution. In essence, he identifies the scale as the problem but then does not consider the possibility of a realistic scale as the solution. While the evidence for evolution is incredibly compelling, it is not necessary that we take mindless adaptability with the fact/value distinction as the foundation for ethics. Incorporating the thought of Medawar, since, abduction is prior to inductive falsifiability in the scientific method – an ability which implies and entails a specifically human way of knowing and ability to see unity 98 and portray creativity – then would it not also be likely that any ethical creed could rest upon this foundation as well? This requires the acceptance that environmental ethics rests on a specifically and uniquely human capability. But the crux of the problem, especially with Callicott, is that he presents the division of facts and values and tries to argue from the “is” to the “ought.” However, the initial step in the way that we discover scientific knowledge begins with our ability to already think and to know in a manner that is ontologically prior to induction in the scientific method. In acknowledging this point, it is not simply to restate Kant’s critique of Hume or to adopt a Kantian model. Kant’s Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals rests on concepts and distinctions made in his Critique of Pure Reason; central to these are his noumenon/phenomenon distinction and his synthetic/analytic distinction. With the noumenon/phenomenon distinction in particular, Kant argues that we cannot know the material world and that we, the rational animal, are distinct because of our ability to reason. Furthermore, because the noumenon (thinking beings) and the phenomenon (the rest of the empirical world) are substantially different, we can never know (in a scientific way) other noumenon, but can only “think” them.191 Because of this distinction, Kant facilitates a further separation of the mind and body, creating a greater divide between humans and other species. Because of the division of Kantian epistemology, I do not wish to suggest that by beginning with the human capacity of abduction and are specifically human way of knowing that we should follow a Kantian model.192 Instead of focusing on the a priori, we can simply acknowledge the unique ability that we have as a species to think creatively and give and abstract 191 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, Translated by Norman Kemp Smith, UK: Palgrave MacMillan, 2007, 268-269. 192 There are other reasons that a Kantian epistemology is unconvincing as well, specifically with regard to his assertion that we cannot make knowledge claims about statements of fact, but only how we perceive things. Drawing on our abilities to inquire and reflect, Bernard Lonergan offers a convincing refutation of Kant’s epistemology in his work: Insight: A Study into Human Understanding, New York: Harper and Row Publishing Inc., 1978, 341-342. 99 meaning. Applying the concepts of the our species as outlines by Rackham and Medawar above, this does not require a separation of our species from the rest of the biotic community in a Cartesian or Kantian manner, but it does allow for a different beginning place for a plausible environmental ethic. Instead of beginning with pure reason, or with the Darwinian model alone, claiming our homogeneity with other species, we begin with our embodied but unique abilities. By beginning with our embodied unique abilities we are still in accordance with the evolutionary theory. In doing so, we do not have to underwrite or apologise for our capacities, nor does it require that we consider ourselves to be completely set apart from the rest of the nonhuman world. However, it does allow for a genuine place of beginning, as Berthold-Bond would argue: an acknowledgement of our subjectivity as the foundation for place-making capacities. Although the adjustment to holistic environmental ethics rests on the recognition of the importance of humanity, this does not mean that we do not have a responsibility to act ethically towards the rest of the biotic community. However, it should be acknowledged that our ability to recognize that we are in community to the other members of the biosphere is through our unique ability to think creatively – a capability which also does set us apart from the rest of the biotic community (or at least as far as we know at this point). Ontologically speaking the ability to see unity and think abductively is prior to the know ability of scientific theories. Because of this ontological priority, the uniqueness of humanity should be applied to an ethical creed, if it is using evolutionary theory as the foundation for ethics. If one is appealing to the scientific method as the justification for ethics then one ought to recognize the first step in the method. Conclusion It is popular and easy to blame anthropocentrism as the reason for the environmental crises that we face today. And while it is clear that addressing a specific human greed and particular set of 100 the human species – it is not clear that it is anthropocentrism properly speaking that is the problem. Assuming that morality is a benefit to the human life and we are considering needs beyond just the material and we are including the poor as members of the humanity then a true anthropocentrism would entail ethical actions towards the rest of the biotic community. Our current consumer driven, industrial production of unnecessary goods, can only be maintained on the backs of exploited labour, which appears to be anti-human or egocentric as opposed to anthropocentric. Thus contrary to the predominant claims that our ethics are anthropocentric, they appear to be inherently anti-human. Genuine anthropocentrism is not the creed that justifies the exploitation of the nonhuman world, but anti-humanism under the guise of meeting human needs is the root of the problem. Even in claiming that the problem is anthropocentrism perpetuates the myth that humanity is not more than the sum of its parts – that very issue that environmental philosophy is trying to resolve with respect to the rest of the nonhuman world. Thus to claim that a natural species, resulting as the evidence would suggest from evolutionary processes, already assumes the reduction of humanity to its chemical or mechanistic parts – an application of Cartesian and Baconian thinking in the effort to solving the problems that result from Cartesian-Baconian distillations. As a beginning point for a logically coherent and plausible environmental ethic, we must develop a human-scaled method of acting and knowing. This beginning place further requires that we act ethically towards members of our own species, in a manner that the Radical Ecologists and Holistic Environmental Ethicists do not call for us to do. They claim that we must learn to cultivate and ethics of care for the biotic community and at the same time dismiss those who are closest in our community. These claims contain logical inconsistencies and do not offer a plausible solution. While the scope of this paper will not allow for the step-by-step break down 101 of what creating a culture of care with a true anthropocentric concern would look like, a genuine anthropocentrism must not be dismissed because of the abuses of a “so-called” anthropocentric creed. 102 Conclusion While anthropocentric ethical frameworks provide an easy scapegoat for the current ecological problems we face, in reality the problem is not quite so simple. The Radical Ecology movement and the Holistic Environmental Ethics movements each blame anthropocentrism as the source of the widespread abuse of the nonhuman world, whereas it is a certain interpretation of humans as simply consumers or users that is the problem. This view is an oversimplification and even abuse of who we are as humans. Both of these movements provide accurate and insightful critiques of philosophical frameworks and historical events that have led to the problems that we currently face. However, each requires that a shift regarding our understanding of humanity be made in order to lend logical coherence and plausibility of application. The Radical Ecology approach primarily requires that we acknowledge that the human species should be given special consideration in order to maintain that we are uniquely capable of causing harm. Once this is acknowledged we can then ask why or in what ways we are unique. With these questions we can begin to consider practical and human approaches to solving ecological problems, recalling the abilities and embodied methods of our species. Likewise, the Holistic Environmental Ethics approach also is too hasty in dismissing elements of the human species. This method is more consistent with the evolutionary theory and scientific method which adds to the plausibility and verifiability of this ethical creed. However, the foundation of ethics should not be empirical verifiability but instead should rest on a philosophical claim; doing so requires that we acknowledge the human-infused elements of knowledge that accompany our philosophical inquiries. The emphasis of the goodness of human action and the immorality of the vast scale of the destruction are invaluable contributions to establishing a coherent and plausible environmental ethic. 103 It is important to acknowledge the uniqueness of the human species in order to develop a plausible and logically coherent environmental ethic. The first step in a practical application or development of this ethic is to adopt a genuine human scale, embracing our physicality and the method of knowing and the human affection that comes from this human scale, which includes adopting many of the earlier philosophical insights that have been dismissed by many modern environmental philosophical systems, often without any argument or rationale. This paper provides arguments that show the necessity of the human scale be included as a premise in establishing a practical and logical environmental solution. What ethical creed this human-scaled value system should follow remains to be established. How to implicate this approach on a practical level working within the existing elements of our society and culture also needs to be established. The step-by-step philosophical foundation and the practical applications require further thought. To reiterate, first we must recognise our place within the biotic community, then embrace our physical humanity, to work towards a moral, logical, and affectionate manner of engaging with the nonhuman world. 104 Bibliography Alexander, Christopher. A Pattern Language: Towns, Building, Construction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977. Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by W. D. Ross. Kitchener: Batoche Books, 1999. Bacon, Sir Francis. Novum Organum [1620]. Edited by Joseph Devey. New York: P. F. Collier & Son, 1902. Berthold-Bond, Daniel. “The Ethics of ‘Place’: Reflections on Bioregionalism.” Environmental Ethics 22, no. 1 (2000): 5-24. Berry, Wendell. “Christianity and the Survival of Creation.” Cross Currents 43, no. 2 (1993): 149-164. Accessed on April 20, 2017. http://www.crosscurrents.org/berry.htm. ——. It All Turns on Affection: The Jefferson Lecture and Other Essays. New York: Counterpoint, 2012. “Biocentrism.” English Oxford Living Dictionaries. Accessed December 31, 2016. https://en.oxforddictionaries.com/definition/biocentrism. Bookchin, Murray. “Social Ecology versus Deep Ecology: A Challenge for the Ecology Movement.” In Green Perspectives: Newsletter of the Green Program Project 4. no. 5. (1999): 281-301. Buell, Lawrence. “America the Beautiful, Jane Adams and John Muir.” In Writing for an Endangered World: Literature, Culture, and Environment in the U.S. and Beyond. Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2001. ——. The Environmental Imagination: Thoreau, Nature Writing, and the Formation of American Culture. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995. Callicott, J. Baird. “Do Deconstructive Ecology and Sociobiology Undermine Leopold’s Land Ethic?” In Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, edited by Michael Zimmerman, 145-164. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1998. ——. “The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic.” In Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, edited by Michael E. Zimmerman, 101-1123. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1998. 105 ——. “Non-Anthropocentric Value Theory and Environmental Ethics.” American Philosophical Quarterly 21, no. 4 (1984): 299-309. Accessed December 28, 2016. www.jstor.org/stable/20014060. Carson, Rachel. Silent Spring. New York: Houghton Mifflin Company, 2002. Chesterton, Gilbert Keith. Orthodoxy. Auckland: Floating Press, 2008. Coleridge, Samuel Taylor. “The Rime of the Ancient Mariner.” In The Norton Anthology English Literature: The Romantic Period. Edited by Stephen Greenblatt, 443-458. New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2012. Cronon, William. “The Trouble with Wilderness; or, Getting Back to the Wrong Nature.” In Uncommon Ground: Rethinking the Human Place in Nature, edited by William Cronon, 69-90. New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 1995. “Deep Ecology.” The Green Fuse/Topics. Accessed December 30, 2016. http://www.thegreenfuse.org/deepecology.htm. Dennett, Daniel C. Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. New York: Simon & Schuster Inc., 1996. Descartes, Rene. Discourse on Method and Meditations on First Philosophy. Translated by Donald A. Cres. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1999. Devall, Bill. “John Muir as Deep Ecologist.” Environmental Review: KER 6, no. 1, (1982): 63 86. Accessed April 3, 2017. http:www.jstor.org/stable/3984050. ——. “The Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement 1960-2000-A Review.” Ethics & the Environment 6, no. 1 (2001): 18-41. Dinkel, Christopher. “Coleridge the Rime, and the Image of God: Humanness as Communion with Creator.” The Friends of Coleridge 34 (2009): 42-48. doi: http://www.friendsofcoleridge.com/index.php?option=com_content&view=article &id=&Itemid=29, “Ecofeminism.” The Green Fuse/Topics. Accessed December 30, 2017. http://www.thegreenfuse.org/ecofem.htm. “Ecology.” Biology Online. http://www.biology-online.org/dictionary/Ecology. 106 Elder, John C. “John Muir and the Literature of Wilderness,” The Massechusetts Review 22, no. 2 (1981): 375-386. Accessed 29-03-2017. www.jstor.org/stable/25089154. Faith, Daniel P. “Biodiversity.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Substantive Revision December 4, 2007. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/biodiversity/. Firth, Roderick. “Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12, no. 3 (1952): 317-345. Fox, Warwick. “The Deep Ecology – Ecofeminism Debate and Its Parallels.” Environmental Ethics 11, no. 1 (1989): 5-25. Gatta, John. Making Nature Sacred: Literature, Religion, and Environment in America from the Puritans to the Present. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. Glasser, Harold. “Demystifying the Critiques of Deep Ecology.” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, edited by Michael E. Zimmerman, 212-226. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1998. Gillroy, John Martin. “Kantian Ethics and Environmental Policy Argument: Autonomy, Ecosystem Integrity, and Our Duties to Nature.” Ethics and the Environment 3, no. 2 (1998): 131-155. Accessed October 15, 2016. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40338948. Guilherme, Alex. “Metaphysics as a Basis for Deep Ecology: An Enquiry into Spinoza’s System.” The Trumpeter 27, no. 3 (2011): 60-78. Harrison, Peter. “Descartes on Animals.” The Philosophical Quarterly (1950-) 42. No. 167 (1992): 219-227. Oxford University Press on behalf of the Scot Philosophical Association and the University of St. Andrews. Accessed June 6, 2017. www.jstor.org/stable/2220217. Hegel, G. W. F. Reason in History: A General Introduction to the Philosophy of History. Translated by Robert S. Hartman. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1997. Holy-Luczaj, Magdalena. “Heidegger’s Support for Deep Ecology Reexamined Once Again: Ontological Egalitarianism, Or Farewell to the Great Chain of Being.” Ethics and the Environment 20, no. 1 (2015): 45-66. Indiana University Press. Accessed: March 4, 2017. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2979/ethicsenviro.20.1.45. Hume, David. Enquiries: Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles 107 of Morals. London: Oxford University Press, 1970. Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Norman Kemp Smith. New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2007. ——. Grounding for the Metaphysical of Morals with On a Supposed Right to Lie because of Philanthropic Concerns. Translated by James W. Ellington. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1993. Kierkegaard, Soren. The Present Age: On the Death of Rebellion. Translated by Alexander Dru. New York: Harper Perennial, 2010. Leopold, Aldo. “The Land Ethic.” A Sand Country Almanac: With Essays on Conservation from Round River. New York: Ballantine Books Inc., 1970. Lonergan, Bernard. Insight: A Study into Human Understanding. New York: Harper and Row Publishing Inc., 1978. MacFarlane, Robert. Landmarks. United Kingdom: Random House, 2015. MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2010. Medawar, P. B. The Uniqueness of the Individual. New York: Basic Books Inc., 1957. Merchant, Carolyn. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology, and the Scientific Revolution. New York: Harper Collins Publishing, 1990. Morris, William. News From Nowhere and Selected Writings and Designs. Edited by Asa Briggs. Markham: Penguin Books, 1984. Muir, John. My First Summer in the Sierra. New York: Modern Library, 2003. “Anthropocentric.” Merriam Webster. Accessed December 30, 2016. https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/anthropocentric. Naess, Arne. “Ecocentrism, Wilderness, and Global Ecosystem Protection.” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, edited by Michal Zimmerman, 245 262. New Jersey: Prentice Hall Inc., 1993. 108 ——. “The Deep Ecological Movement: Some Philosophical Aspects.” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, edited by Michael E. Zimmerman, 193-211. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1993. Nagel, Thomas. “What it is like to be a bat?” The Philosophical Review 83, no. 4 (1974): 435-50. Nelson, Michael P. “Aldo Leopold, Environmental Ethics, and the Land Ethic.” Wildlife Society Bulletin (1973-2006) 26, no. 4 (1998): 741-744. Accessed December 1, 2016. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3783545. ——. “Deep Ecology,” Encyclopedia of Environmental Ethics and Philosophy (2008): 206-211. http://www.uky.edu/OtherOrgs/AppalFor/Readings/240%20-%20Reading%20%20Deep%20Ecology.pdf ——. “Holists and Fascists and Paper Tigers…Oh My!” Ethics and the Environment 1, no. 2 (1996): 103-117. Accessed November 16, 2016. http://www.jstor.org/stable/27766017. Nocera, Joseph J. Jules M. Blais, David V. Beresford, Leah K. Finity, Christopher Grooms, Lynda E. Kimpe, Kurt Kyser, Neal Michelutti, Matthew W. Reudink, John P. Smol, “Historical pesticide applications coincided with an altered diet of aerially foraging qinsectivorous chimney swifts.” The Royal Society (2012): 1-7 DOI: 10.1098/rspb.2012.0445. Plato. The Republic. In The Dialogues of Plato in Four Volumes: Volume II. Translated by B. Jowett. London: Oxford University Press, 1964. Polanyi, Michael. The Study of Man. Oxford: Martino Publishing, 2014. ——. The Tacit Dimension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009. Preston, Christopher J. Grounding Knowledge: Environmental Philosophy, Epistemology, and Place. London: The University of Georgia Press, 2003. Rackham, Oliver. The History of the Countryside: The Class History of Britain’s Landscape, Flora, and Fauna. London: The Orion Publishing Group Ltd., 1988. Ratzsch, Del. “Humanness in the Heart: Where Science and Religion Fuse.” In The Believing Primate: Scientific, Philosophical, and Theological Reflections on the Origin of Religion, edited by Jeffrey Schloss and Michael J. Murray, 215-245. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010. Rigby, Kate. “Ecocriticism.” In Literary and Cultural Criticism at the Twenty-First Century, 109 edited by Julian Wolfreys, 151-178. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2002. Rolston, III, Holmes. “Challenges in Environmental Ethics.” In Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, edited by Michael E. Zimmerman, 124-144. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1998. ——. “Ecology.” In Ethics, Science, Technology, and Engineering: A Global Resource 2 edited by Holbrook, J. Britt and Carl Mitchams. Michigan: Macmillan Reference (2015): 27-31. ——. Christopher Preston, and Dan Spencer. “The Ethical Imperatives of Wilderness.” Video presentation. 1:14:46. Accessed: May 12, 2017. Published April 14, 2015. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Ptq8BS91fko. ——. “The Anthropocene! Beyond the Natural?” In The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics, edited by Stephen M. Gardiner and Allen Thompson, 62-73. New York: Oxford University Press, 2017. Schumacher, E. F. Small is Beautiful: Economics as if People Mattered. New York: Harper and Row, 1973. Seddon, Keith. Lao Tzu & Tao Te Ching. Lulu: 2006. Sessions, George. “Ecocentrism, Wilderness, and the Global Ecosystem Protection.” In Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, edited by Michael Zimmerman, 245-262. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1993. ——. “The Deep Ecology Movement: A Review.” Environmental Review: ER 11, no. 2 (1987): 105-125. Accessed April 3, 2017. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3984023. Sober, Elliot. Core Issues in Philosophy: A Text with Readings. New Jersey: Pearson, 2012. Scruton, Roger. How to Think Seriously About the Planet: The Case for Environmental Conservatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012. Singer, Peter. “The Environment.” In Practical Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. “Social Ecology.” The Green Fuse/Topics. Accessed December 30, 2016. http://www.thegreenfuse.org/socialecology.htm. Taylor, Paul W. “The Ethics of Respect for Nature.” Environmental Ethics 3, no. 3 (1981): 197 110 218. Thoreau, Henry David. Walden; Or, Life in the Woods. New York: Dover Publications, 1995. Van Inwagen, Peter. “Objectivity.” http://jeffsnapper.org/assets/vaninwagenobj.pdf. Waller, David. “A Vegetarian Critique of Deep and Social Ecology.” Ethics and the Environment 2, no. 2 (1997): 187-197. Accessed April 4, 2017. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40338940. White Jr., Lynn. “The Historical Roots of Our Ecological Crisis.” Science New Series 155 no. 3767 (1967): 1203-1207. Published by American Association for the Advancement of Science. Accessed November 11, 2016. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1720120. Warren Karen J. and Jim Cheney, “Ecological Feminism and Ecosystem Ecology,” Hypatia 6, no. 1 (1991): 179-197. Accessed: April 3, 2017. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3810040. Warren, Karen J. “The Power and the Promise of Ecological Feminism.” In Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology edited by Michael Zimmerman, 325-344. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1998. Zimmerman, Michael. “General Introduction,” Environmental Ethics: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, 1-16. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1998. 111